|
[4:] Not that a Hindu
could not be taught the sense of duty to fallen humanity, but the
trouble is that no amount of sense of duty can enable him to overcome
his duty to preserve his caste. Caste is, therefore, the real
explanation as to why the Hindu has let the savage remain a savage in
the midst of his civilization without blushing, or without feeling any
sense of remorse or repentance. The Hindu has not realized that these
aborigines are a source of potential danger. If these savages remain
savages, they may not do any harm to the Hindus. But if they are
reclaimed by non-Hindus and converted to their faiths, they will swell
the ranks of the enemies of the Hindus. If this happens, the Hindu will
have to thank himself and his Caste System.
9 [The higher castes have conspired to keep the lower castes down]
|
|
[1:] Not only has the Hindu
made no effort for the humanitarian cause of civilizing the savages,
but the higher-caste Hindus have deliberately prevented the lower castes
who are within the pale of Hinduism from rising to the cultural level
of the higher castes. I will give two instances, one of the Sonars and the other of the Pathare Prabhus. Both are communities quite well-known in Maharashtra.
Like the rest of the communities desiring to raise their status, these
two communities were at one time endeavouring to adopt some of the ways
and habits of the Brahmins.
|
|
[2:] The Sonars were styling themselves Daivadnya Brahmins and were wearing their “dhotis” with folds in them, and using the word namaskar for salutation. Both the folded way of wearing the “dhoti” and the namaskar were
special to the Brahmins. The Brahmins did not like this imitation and
this attempt by Sonars to pass off as Brahmins. Under the authority of
the Peshwas,
the Brahmins successfully put down this attempt on the part of the
Sonars to adopt the ways of the Brahmins. They even got the President of
the Councils of the East India Company’s settlement in Bombay to issue a prohibitory order against the Sonars residing in Bombay.
|
|
[3:] At one time the Pathare Prabhus
had widow-remarriage as a custom of their caste. This custom of
widow-remarriage was later on looked upon as a mark of social
inferiority by some members of the caste, especially because it was
contrary to the custom prevalent among the Brahmins.
With the object of raising the status of their community, some Pathare
Prabhus sought to stop this practice of widow-remarriage that was
prevalent in their caste. The community was divided into two camps, one
for and the other against the innovation. The Peshwas
took the side of those in favour of widow-remarriage, and thus
virtually prohibited the Pathare Prabhus from following the ways of the
Brahmins.
|
|
[4:] The Hindus criticise the Mohammedans
for having spread their religion by the use of the sword. They also
ridicule Christianity on the score of the Inquisition. But really
speaking, who is better and more worthy of our respect—the Mohammedans
and Christians who attempted to thrust down the throats of unwilling
persons what they regarded as necessary for their salvation, or the Hindu
who would not spread the light, who would endeavour to keep others in
darkness, who would not consent to share his intellectual and social
inheritance with those who are ready and willing to make it a part of
their own make-up? I have no hesitation in saying that if the Mohammedan
has been cruel, the Hindu has been mean; and meanness is worse than
cruelty.
10 [Caste prevents Hinduism from being a missionary religion]
|
|
[1:] Whether the Hindu
religion was or was not a missionary religion has been a controversial
issue. Some hold the view that it was never a missionary religion.
Others hold that it was. That the Hindu religion was once a missionary
religion must be admitted. It could not have spread over the face of
India, if it was not a missionary religion. That today it is not a
missionary religion is also a fact which must be accepted. The question
therefore is not whether or not the Hindu religion was a missionary
religion. The real question is, why did the Hindu religion cease to be a
missionary religion?
|
|
[2:] My answer is this: the Hindu religion ceased to be a missionary religion when the Caste System
grew up among the Hindus. Caste is inconsistent with conversion.
Inculcation of beliefs and dogmas is not the only problem that is
involved in conversion. To find a place for the convert in the social
life of the community is another, and a much more important, problem
that arises in connection with conversion. That problem is where to
place the convert, in what caste? It is a problem which must baffle
every Hindu wishing to make aliens converts to his religion.
|
|
[3:] Unlike a club, the membership of a caste
is not open to all and sundry. The law of Caste confines its membership
to persons born in the caste. Castes are autonomous, and there is no
authority anywhere to compel a caste to admit a new-comer to its social
life. Hindu
Society being a collection of castes, and each caste being a closed
corporation, there is no place for a convert. Thus it is the caste which
has prevented the Hindus
from expanding and from absorbing other religious communities. So long
as Caste remains, Hindu religion cannot be made a missionary religion,
and Shudhi will be both a folly and a futility.
11 [Caste deprives Hindus of mutual help, trust, and fellow-feeling]
|
|
[1:] The reasons which have made Shudhi impossible for Hindus are also responsible for making Sanghatan impossible. The idea underlying Sanghatan is to remove from the mind of the Hindu
that timidity and cowardice which so painfully mark him off from the
Mohammedan and the Sikh, and which have led him to adopt the low ways of
treachery and cunning for protecting himself. The question naturally
arises: From where does the Sikh or the Mohammedan derive his strength,
which makes him brave and fearless? I am sure it is not due to relative
superiority of physical strength, diet, or drill. It is due to the
strength arising out of the feeling that all Sikhs will come to the rescue of a Sikh when he is in danger, and that all Mohammedans will rush to save a Muslim if he is attacked.
|
|
[2:] The Hindu
can derive no such strength. He cannot feel assured that his fellows
will come to his help. Being one and fated to be alone, he remains
powerless, develops timidity and cowardice, and in a fight surrenders or
runs away. The Sikh as well as the Muslim
stands fearless and gives battle, because he knows that though one he
will not be alone. The presence of this belief in the one helps him to
hold out, and the absence of it in the other makes him to give way.
|
|
[3:] If you pursue this matter further and
ask what is it that enables the Sikh and the Mohammedan to feel so
assured, and why is the Hindu
filled with such despair in the matter of help and assistance, you will
find that the reasons for this difference lie in the difference in
their associated mode of living. The associated mode of life practised
by the Sikhs and the Mohammedans produces fellow-feeling. The associated mode of life of the Hindus does not. Among Sikhs and Muslims there is a social cement which makes them Bhais. Among Hindus
there is no such cement, and one Hindu does not regard another Hindu as
his Bhai. This explains why a Sikh says and feels that one Sikh, or one
Khalsa, is equal to sava lakh
men. This explains why one Mohammedan is equal to a crowd of Hindus.
This difference is undoubtedly a difference due to Caste. So long as
Caste remains, there will be no Sanghatan; and so long as there is no Sanghatan the Hindu will remain weak and meek.
|
|
[4:] The Hindus
claim to be a very tolerant people. In my opinion this is a mistake. On
many occasions they can be intolerant, and if on some occasions they
are tolerant, that is because they are too weak to oppose or too
indifferent to oppose. This indifference of the Hindus has become so
much a part of their nature that a Hindu will quite meekly tolerate an
insult as well as a wrong. You see amongst them, to use the words of Morris,
“The great treading down the little, the strong beating down the weak,
cruel men fearing not, kind men daring not and wise men caring not.”
With the Hindu Gods all-forbearing, it is not difficult to imagine the
pitiable condition of the wronged and the oppressed among the Hindus.
Indifferentism is the worst kind of disease that can infect a people.
Why is the Hindu so indifferent? In my opinion this indifferentism is
the result of the Caste System, which has made Sanghatan and co-operation even for a good cause impossible.
12 [Caste is a powerful weapon for preventing all reform]
|
|
[1:] The assertion by the individual of his
own opinions and beliefs, his own independence and interest—as over
against group standards, group authority, and group interests—is the
beginning of all reform. But whether the reform will continue depends
upon what scope the group affords for such individual assertion. If the
group is tolerant and fair-minded in dealing with such individuals, they
will continue to assert [their beliefs], and in the end will succeed in
converting their fellows. On the other hand if the group is intolerant,
and does not bother about the means it adopts to stifle such
individuals, they will perish and the reform will die out.
|
|
[2:] Now a caste has an unquestioned right to
excommunicate any man who is guilty of breaking the rules of the caste;
and when it is realized that excommunication involves a complete cesser
[=cessation] of social intercourse, it will be agreed that as a form of
punishment there is really little to choose between excommunication and
death. No wonder individual Hindus have not had the courage to assert their independence by breaking the barriers of Caste.
|
|
[3:] It is true that man cannot get on with
his fellows. But it is also true that he cannot do without them. He
would like to have the society of his fellows on his terms. If he cannot
get it on his terms, then he will be ready to have it on any terms,
even amounting to complete surrender. This is because he cannot do
without society. A caste is ever ready to take advantage of the
helplessness of a man, and to insist upon complete conformity to its
code in letter and in spirit.
|
|
[4:] A caste can easily organize itself into a
conspiracy to make the life of a reformer a hell; and if a conspiracy
is a crime, I do not understand why such a nefarious act as an attempt
to excommunicate a person for daring to act contrary to the rules of
caste should not be made an offence punishable in law. But as it is,
even law gives each caste an autonomy to regulate its membership and
punish dissenters with excommunication. Caste in the hands of the
orthodox has been a powerful weapon for persecuting the reformers and
for killing all reform.
13 [Caste destroys public spirit, public opinion, and public charity]
|
|
[1:] The effect of caste on the ethics of the Hindus
is simply deplorable. Caste has killed public spirit. Caste has
destroyed the sense of public charity. Caste has made public opinion
impossible. A Hindu’s
public is his caste. His responsibility is only to his caste. His
loyalty is restricted only to his caste. Virtue has become caste-ridden,
and morality has become caste-bound. There is no sympathy for the
deserving. There is no appreciation of the meritorious. There is no
charity to the needy. Suffering as such calls for no response. There is
charity, but it begins with the caste and ends with the caste. There is
sympathy, but not for men of other castes.
|
|
[2:] Would a Hindu acknowledge and follow the leadership of a great and good man? The case of a Mahatma apart, the answer must be that he will follow a leader if he is a man of his caste. A Brahmin will follow a leader only if he is a Brahmin, a Kayastha
if he is a Kayastha, and so on. The capacity to appreciate merits in a
man, apart from his caste, does not exist in a Hindu. There is
appreciation of virtue, but only when the man is a fellow caste-man. The
whole morality is as bad as tribal morality. My caste-man, right or
wrong; my caste-man, good or bad. It is not a case of standing by virtue
or not standing by vice. It is a case of standing by, or not standing
by, the caste. Have not Hindus committed treason against their country
in the interests of their caste?
13 [Caste destroys public spirit, public opinion, and public charity]
|
|
[1:] The effect of caste on the ethics of the Hindus
is simply deplorable. Caste has killed public spirit. Caste has
destroyed the sense of public charity. Caste has made public opinion
impossible. A Hindu’s
public is his caste. His responsibility is only to his caste. His
loyalty is restricted only to his caste. Virtue has become caste-ridden,
and morality has become caste-bound. There is no sympathy for the
deserving. There is no appreciation of the meritorious. There is no
charity to the needy. Suffering as such calls for no response. There is
charity, but it begins with the caste and ends with the caste. There is
sympathy, but not for men of other castes.
|
|
[2:] Would a Hindu acknowledge and follow the leadership of a great and good man? The case of a Mahatma apart, the answer must be that he will follow a leader if he is a man of his caste. A Brahmin will follow a leader only if he is a Brahmin, a Kayastha
if he is a Kayastha, and so on. The capacity to appreciate merits in a
man, apart from his caste, does not exist in a Hindu. There is
appreciation of virtue, but only when the man is a fellow caste-man. The
whole morality is as bad as tribal morality. My caste-man, right or
wrong; my caste-man, good or bad. It is not a case of standing by virtue
or not standing by vice. It is a case of standing by, or not standing
by, the caste. Have not Hindus committed treason against their country
in the interests of their caste?
14 [My ideal: a society based on Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity]
|
|
[1:] I would not be surprized if some of you
have grown weary listening to this tiresome tale of the sad effects
which caste has produced. There is nothing new in it. I will therefore
turn to the constructive side of the problem. What is your ideal society
if you do not want caste, is a question that is bound to be asked of
you. If you ask me, my ideal would be a society based on Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity. And why not?
|
|
[2:] What objection can there be to
Fraternity? I cannot imagine any. An ideal society should be mobile,
should be full of channels for conveying a change taking place in one
part to other parts. In an ideal society there should be many interests
consciously communicated and shared. There should be varied and free
points of contact with other modes of association. In other words there
must be social endosmosis. This is fraternity, which is only another
name for democracy. Democracy is not merely a form of government. It is
primarily a mode of associated living, of conjoint communicated
experience. It is essentially an attitude of respect and reverence
towards one’s fellow men.
|
|
[3:] Any objection to Liberty? Few object to
liberty in the sense of a right to free movement, in the sense of a
right to life and limb. There is no objection to liberty in the sense of
a right to property, tools, and materials, as being necessary for
earning a living, to keep the body in a due state of health. Why not
allow a person the liberty to benefit from an effective and competent
use of a person’s powers? The supporters of Caste who would allow
liberty in the sense of a right to life, limb, and property, would not
readily consent to liberty in this sense, inasmuch as it involves
liberty to choose one’s profession.
|
|
[4:] But to object to this kind of liberty is
to perpetuate slavery. For slavery does not merely mean a legalized
form of subjection. It means a state of society in which some men are
forced to accept from others the purposes which control their conduct.
This condition obtains even where there is no slavery in the legal
sense. It is found where, as in the Caste System, some persons are compelled to carry on certain prescribed callings which are not of their choice.
|
|
[5:] Any objection to equality? This has
obviously been the most contentious part of the slogan of the French
Revolution. The objections to equality may be sound, and one may have to
admit that all men are not equal. But what of that? Equality may be a
fiction, but nonetheless one must accept it as the governing principle. A
man’s power is dependent upon (1) physical heredity; (2) social
inheritance or endowment in the form of parental care, education,
accumulation of scientific knowledge, everything which enables him to be
more efficient than the savage; and finally, (3) on his own efforts. In
all these three respects men are undoubtedly unequal. But the question
is, shall we treat them as unequal because they are unequal? This is a
question which the opponents of equality must answer.
|
|
[6:] From the standpoint of the
individualist, it may be just to treat men unequally so far as their
efforts are unequal. It may be desirable to give as much incentive as
possible to the full development of everyone’s powers. But what would
happen if men were treated as unequally as they are unequal in the first
two respects? It is obvious that those individuals also in whose favour
there is birth, education, family name, business connections, and
inherited wealth, would be selected in the race. But selection under
such circumstances would not be a selection of the able. It would be the
selection of the privileged. The reason, therefore, which requires that
in the third respect [of those described in the paragraph above] we
should treat men unequally, demands that in the first two respects we
should treat men as equally as possible.
|
|
[7:] On the other hand, it can be urged that
if it is good for the social body to get the most out of its members, it
can get the most out of them only by making them equal as far as
possible at the very start of the race. That is one reason why we cannot
escape equality. But there is another reason why we must accept
equality. A statesman is concerned with vast numbers of people. He has
neither the time nor the knowledge to draw fine distinctions and to
treat each one equitably, i.e. according to need or according to
capacity. However desirable or reasonable an equitable treatment of men
may be, humanity is not capable of assortment and classification. The
statesman, therefore, must follow some rough and ready rule, and that
rough and ready rule is to treat all men alike, not because they are
alike but because classification and assortment is impossible. The
doctrine of equality is glaringly fallacious but, taking all in all, it
is the only way a statesman can proceed in politics—which is a severely
practical affair and which demands a severely practical test.
15 [The Arya Samajists’ “Chaturvarnya” retains the old bad caste labels]
|
|
[1:] But there is a set of reformers who hold out a different ideal. They go by the name of the Arya Samajists, and their ideal of social organization is what is called Chaturvarnya,
or the division of society into four classes instead of the four
thousand castes that we have in India. To make it more attractive and to
disarm opposition, the protagonists of Chaturvarnya
take great care to point out that their Chaturvarnya is based not on
birth but on guna (worth). At the outset, I must confess that
notwithstanding the worth-basis of this Chaturvarnya, it is an ideal to
which I cannot reconcile myself.
|
|
[2:] In the first place, if under the Chaturvarnya of the Arya Samajists an individual is to take his place in the Hindu Society according to his worth, I do not understand why the Arya Samajists insist upon labelling men as Brahmin, Kshatriya, Vaishya and Shudra.
A learned man would be honoured without his being labelled a Brahmin. A
soldier would be respected without his being designated a Kshatriya. If
European society honours its soldiers and its servants without giving
them permanent labels, why should Hindu Society find it difficult to do
so, is a question which Arya Samajists have not cared to consider.
|
|
[3:] There is another objection to the
continuance of these labels. All reform consists in a change in the
notions, sentiments, and mental attitudes of the people towards men and
things. It is common experience that certain names become associated
with certain notions and sentiments which determine a person’s attitude
towards men and things. The names Brahmin, Kshatriya, Vaishya, and Shudra are names which are associated with a definite and fixed notion in the mind of every Hindu. That notion is that of a hierarchy based on birth.
|
|
[4:] So long as these names continue, Hindus will continue to think of the Brahmin, Kshatriya, Vaishya, and Shudra as hierarchical divisions of high and low, based on birth, and to act accordingly. The Hindu
must be made to unlearn all this. But how can this happen, if the old
labels remain, and continue to recall to his mind old notions? If new
notions are to be inculcated in the minds of people, it is necessary to
give them new names. To continue the old names is to make the reform
futile. To allow this Chaturvarnya
based on worth to be designated by such stinking labels as Brahmin,
Kshatriya, Vaishya, Shudra, indicative of social divisions based on
birth, is a snare.
16 [”Chaturvarnya” would face impossible difficulties in practice]
|
|
[1:] To me this Chaturvarnya
with its old labels is utterly repellent, and my whole being rebels
against it. But I do not wish to rest my objection to Chaturvarnya on
mere grounds of sentiments. There are more solid grounds on which I rely
for my opposition to it. A close examination of this ideal has
convinced me that as a system of social organization, Chaturvarnya is
impracticable, is harmful, and has turned out to be a miserable failure.
From a practical point of view, the system of Chaturvarnya raises
several difficulties which its protagonists [=advocates] do not seem to
have taken into account. The principle underlying Caste is fundamentally
different from the principle underlying Chaturvarnya. Not only are they fundamentally different, but they are also fundamentally opposed.
|
|
[2:] The former [=Chaturvarnya] is based on
worth. How are you going to compel people who have acquired a higher
status based on birth, without reference to their worth, to vacate that
status? How are you going to compel people to recognize the status due
to a man, in accordance with his worth, who is occupying a lower status
based on his birth? For this, you must first break up the Caste System, in order to be able to establish the Chaturvarnya system. How are you going to reduce the four thousand castes, based on birth, to the four Varnas, based on worth? This is the first difficulty which the protagonists of the Chaturvarnya must grapple with.
|
|
[3:] There is a second difficulty which the protagonists of Chaturvarnya
must grapple with, if they wish to make the establishment of
Chaturvarnya a success. Chaturvarnya pre-supposes that you can classify
people into four definite classes. Is this possible? In this respect,
the ideal of Chaturvarnya has, as you will see, a close affinity to the
Platonic ideal. To Plato, men fell by nature into three classes. In some
individuals, he believed, mere appetites dominated. He assigned them to
the labouring and trading classes. Others revealed to him that over and
above appetites, they had a courageous disposition. He classed them as
defenders in war and guardians of internal peace. Others showed a
capacity to grasp the universal reason underlying things. He made them
the law-givers of the people.
|
|
[4:] The criticism to which Plato’s Republic is subject, is also
the criticism which must apply to the system of Chaturvarnya,
insofar as it proceeds upon the possibility of an accurate
classification of men into four distinct classes. The chief criticism
against Plato is that his idea of lumping individuals into a few
sharply-marked-off classes is a very superficial view of man and his
powers. Plato had no perception of the uniqueness of every individual,
of his incommensurability with others, of each individual as forming a
class of his own. He had no recognition of the infinite diversity of
active tendencies, and the combination of tendencies of which an
individual is capable. To him, there were types of faculties or powers
in the individual constitution.
|
|
[5:] All this is demonstrably wrong. Modem
science has shown that the lumping together of individuals into a few
sharply-marked-off classes is a superficial view of man, not worthy of
serious consideration. Consequently, the utilization of the qualities of
individuals is incompatible with their stratification by classes, since
the qualities of individuals are so variable. Chaturvarnya
must fail for the very reason for which Plato’s Republic must
fail—namely, that it is not possible to pigeonhole men, according as
they belong to one class or the other. That it is impossible to
accurately classify people into four definite classes, is proved by the
fact that the original four classes have now become four thousand
castes.
|
|
[6:] There is a third difficulty in the way of the establishment of the system of Chaturvarnya.
How are you going to maintain the system of Chaturvarnya, supposing it
was established? One important requirement for the successful working of
Chaturvarnya is the maintenance of the penal system which could
maintain it by its sanction. The system of Chaturvarnya must perpetually
face the problem of the transgressor. Unless there is a penalty
attached to the act of transgression, men will not keep to their
respective classes. The whole system will break down, being contrary to
human nature. Chaturvarnya cannot subsist by its own inherent goodness.
It must be enforced by law.
|
|
[7:] That without penal sanction the ideal of Chaturvarnya cannot be realized, is proved by the story in the Ramayana of Rama killing Shambuka. Some people seem to blame Rama because he wantonly and without reason killed Shambuka. But to blame Rama for killing Shambuka is to misunderstand the whole situation. Ram Raj
was a Raj based on Chaturvarnya. As a king, Rama was bound to maintain
Chaturvarnya. It was his duty therefore to kill Shambuka, the Shudra
who had transgressed his class and wanted to be a Brahmin. This is the
reason why Rama killed Shambuka. But this also shows that penal sanction
is necessary for the maintenance of Chaturvarnya. Not only penal
sanction is necessary, but the penalty of death is necessary. That is
why Rama did not inflict on Shambuka a lesser punishment. That is why
the Manu-Smriti
prescribes such heavy sentences as cutting off the tongue, or pouring
of molten lead in the ears, of the Shudra who recites or hears the Veda.
The supporters of Chaturvarnya must give an assurance that they could
successfully classify men, and that they could induce modern society in
the twentieth century to re-forge the penal sanctions of the Manu-Smriti.
|
|
[8:] The protagonists of Chaturvarnya do not seem to have considered what is to happen to women in their system. Are they also to be divided into four classes, Brahmin, Kshatriya, Vaishya and Shudra?
Or are they to be allowed to take the status of their husbands? If the
status of the woman is to be the consequence of marriage, what becomes
of the underlying principle of Chaturvarnya—namely, that the status of a
person should be based upon the worth of that person? If they are to be
classified according to their worth, is their classification to be
nominal or real?
|
|
[9:] If it is to be nominal, then it is useless; and then the protagonists of Chaturvarnya
must admit that their system does not apply to women. If it is real,
are the protagonists of Chaturvarnya prepared to follow the logical
consequences of applying it to women? They must be prepared to have
women priests and women soldiers. Hindu
society has grown accustomed to women teachers and women barristers. It
may grow accustomed to women brewers and women butchers. But he would
be a bold person who would say that it will allow women priests and
women soldiers. But that will be the logical outcome of applying
Chaturvarnya to women. Given these difficulties, I think no one except a
congenital idiot could hope for and believe in a successful
regeneration of the Chaturvarnya.
17 [”Chaturvarnya” would be the most vicious system for the Shudras]
|
|
[1:] Assuming that Chaturvarnya is practicable, I contend that it is the most vicious system. That the Brahmins should cultivate knowledge, that the Kshatriya should bear arms, that the Vaishya should trade, and that the Shudra
should serve, sounds as though it was a system of division of labour.
Whether the theory was intended to state that the Shudra need not, or
whether it was intended to lay down that he must not, is an interesting
question. The defenders of Chaturvarnya give it the first meaning. They
say, why need the Shudra trouble to acquire wealth, when the three
[higher] Varnas are there to support him? Why need the Shudra bother to
take to education, when there is the Brahmin to whom he can go when the
occasion for reading or writing arises? Why need the Shudra worry to arm
himself, when there is the Kshatriya to protect him? The theory of
Chaturvarnya, understood in this sense, may be said to look upon the
Shudra as the ward and the three [higher] Varnas as his guardians. Thus
interpreted, it is a simple, elevating, and alluring theory.
|
|
[2:] Assuming this to be the correct view of the underlying conception of Chaturvarnya, it seems to me that the system is neither fool-proof nor knave-proof. What is to happen if the Brahmins, Vaishyas, and Kshatriyas
fail to pursue knowledge, to engage in economic enterprise, and to be
efficient soldiers, which are their respective functions? Contrary-wise,
suppose that they discharge their functions, but flout their duty to
the Shudra
or to one another; what is to happen to the Shudra if the three classes
refuse to support him on fair terms, or combine to keep him down? Who
is to safeguard the interests of the Shudra—or for that matter, those
of the Vaishya and Kshatriya—when the person who is trying to take
advantage of his ignorance is the Brahmin? Who is to defend the liberty
of the Shudra—and for that matter, of the Brahmin and the Vaishya—when
the person who is robbing him of it is the Kshatriya?
|
|
[3:] Inter-dependence of one class on another
class is inevitable. Even dependence of one class upon another may
sometimes become allowable. But why make one person depend upon another
in the matter of his vital needs? Education, everyone must have. Means
of defence, everyone must have. These are the paramount requirements of
every man for his self-preservation. How can the fact that his neighbour
is educated and armed help a man who is uneducated and disarmed? The
whole theory is absurd. These are the questions which the defenders of Chaturvarnya
do not seem to be troubled about. But they are very pertinent
questions. Assuming that in their conception of Chaturvarnya the
relationship between the different classes is that of ward and guardian,
and that this is the real conception underlying Chaturvarnya, it must
be admitted that it makes no provision to safeguard the interests of the
ward from the misdeeds of the guardian.
|
|
[4:] Whether or not the relationship of guardian and ward was the real underlying conception on which Chaturvarnya was based, there is no doubt that in practice the relation was that of master and servants. The three classes, Brahmins,
Kshatriyas, and Vaishyas, although not very happy in their mutual
relationship, managed to work by compromise. The Brahmin flattered the Kshatriya, and both let the Vaishya live in order to be able to live upon him. But the three agreed to beat down the Shudra.
He was not allowed to acquire wealth, lest he should be independent of
the three [higher] Varnas. He was prohibited from acquiring knowledge,
lest he should keep a steady vigil regarding his interests. He was
prohibited from bearing arms, lest he should have the means to rebel
against their authority. That this is how the Shudras were treated by
the Tryavarnikas is evidenced by the Laws of Manu. There is no code of laws more infamous regarding social rights than the Laws of Manu. Any instance from anywhere of social injustice must pale before it.
|
|
[5:] Why have the mass of people tolerated
the social evils to which they have been subjected? There have been
social revolutions in other countries of the world. Why have there not
been social revolutions in India, is a question which has incessantly
troubled me. There is only one answer which I can give, and it is that
the lower classes of Hindus have been completely disabled for direct action on account of this wretched Caste System.
They could not bear arms, and without arms they could not rebel. They
were all ploughmen—or rather, condemned to be ploughmen—and they never
were allowed to convert their ploughshares into swords. They had no
bayonets, and therefore everyone who chose, could and did sit upon them.
On account of the Caste System,
they could receive no education. They could not think out or know the
way to their salvation. They were condemned to be lowly; and not knowing
the way of escape, and not having the means of escape, they became
reconciled to eternal servitude, which they accepted as their
inescapable fate.
|
|
[6:] It is true that even in Europe the
strong has not shrunk from the exploitation—nay, the spoliation—of the
weak. But in Europe, the strong have never contrived to make the weak
helpless against exploitation so shamelessly as was the case in India
among the Hindus. Social war has been raging between the strong and the
weak far more violently in Europe than it has ever been in India. Yet
the weak in Europe has had in his freedom of military service, his
physical weapon; in suffering, his political weapon; and in education,
his moral weapon. These three weapons for emancipation were never
withheld by the strong from the weak in Europe. All these weapons were,
however, denied to the masses in India by the Caste System.
|
|
[7:] There cannot be a more degrading system of social organization than the Caste System.
It is the system which deadens, paralyses, and cripples the people,
[keeping them] from helpful activity. This is no exaggeration. History
bears ample evidence. There is only one period in Indian history which
is a period of freedom, greatness, and glory. That is the period of the Mourya Empire. At all other times the country suffered from defeat and darkness. But the Mourya period was a period when the Caste System
was completely annihilated—when the Shudras, who constituted the mass
of the people, came into their own and became the rulers of the country.
The period of defeat and darkness is the period when the Caste System flourished, to the damnation of the greater part of the people of the country.
18 [”Chaturvarnya” is nothing new; it is as old as the Vedas]
|
|
[1:] Chaturvarnya is not new. It is as old as the Vedas. That is one of the reasons why we are asked by the Arya Samajists
to consider its claims. Judging from the past, as a system of social
organization it has been tried and it has failed. How many times have
the Brahmins annihilated the seed of the Kshatriyas! How many times have the Kshatriyas annihilated the Brahmins! The Mahabharata and the Puranas
are full of incidents of the strife between the Brahmins and the
Kshatriyas. They even quarreled over such petty questions as to who
should salute first, as to who should give way first, the Brahmins or
the Kshatriyas, when the two met in the street.
|
|
[2:] Not only was the Brahmin an eyesore to the Kshatriya
and the Kshatriya an eyesore to the Brahmin, it seems that the
Kshatriyas had become tyrannical, and the masses, disarmed as they were
under the system of Chaturvarnya, were praying to Almighty God for relief from their tyranny. The Bhagwat tells us very definitely that Krishna had taken avatar
for one sacred purpose: and that was, to annihilate the Kshatriyas.
With these instances of rivalry and enmity between the different Varnas
before us, I do not understand how anyone can hold out Chaturvarnya as
an ideal to be aimed at, or as a pattern on which the Hindu Society should be remodelled.
19 [Caste among Hindus is not the same as “caste” among non-Hindus]
|
|
[1:] I have dealt with those, those who are outside your group [=the Mandal]
and whose hostility to your ideal [=the destruction of Caste] is quite
open. There appear to be others who are neither without you nor with
you. I was hesitating whether I should deal with their point of view.
But on further consideration I have come to the conclusion that I must,
and that for two reasons. Firstly, their attitude to the problem of
caste is not merely an attitude of neutrality, but is an attitude of
armed neutrality. Secondly, they probably represent a considerable body
of people. Of these, there is one set which finds nothing peculiar nor
odious in the Caste System of the Hindus. Such Hindus cite the case of Muslims, Sikhs, and Christians, and find comfort in the fact that they too have castes amongst them.
|
|
[2:] In considering this question, you must
at the outset bear in mind that nowhere is human society one single
whole. It is always plural. In the world of action, the individual is
one limit and society the other. Between them lie all sorts of
associative arrangements of lesser and larger scope—families,
friendships, co-operative associations, business combines, political
parties, bands of thieves and robbers. These small groups are usually
firmly welded together, and are often as exclusive as castes. They have a
narrow and intensive code, which is often anti-social. This is true of
every society, in Europe as well as in Asia. The question to be asked in
determining whether a given society is an ideal society is not whether
there are groups in it, because groups exist in all societies.
|
|
[3:] The questions to be asked in determining
what is an ideal society are: How numerous and varied are the interests
which are consciously shared by the groups? How full and free is the
interplay with other forms of associations? Are the forces that separate
groups and classes more numerous than the forces that unite them? What
social significance is attached to this group life? Is its exclusiveness
a matter of custom and convenience, or is it a matter of religion? It
is in the light of these questions that one must decide whether caste
among Non-Hindus is the same as Caste among Hindus.
|
|
[4:] If we apply these considerations to castes among Mohammedans, Sikhs, and Christians on the one hand, and to castes among Hindus
on the other, you will find that caste among Non-Hindus is
fundamentally different from caste among Hindus. First, the ties which
consciously make the Hindus
hold together are non-existent, while among Non-Hindus there are many
that hold them together. The strength of a society depends upon the
presence of points of contact, possibilities of interaction, between
different groups which exist in it. These are what Carlyle
calls “organic filaments”—i.e., the elastic threads which help to bring
the disintegrating elements together and to reunite them. There is no
integrating force among the Hindus
to counteract the disintegration caused by caste. While among the
Non-Hindus there are plenty of these organic filaments which bind them
together.
|
|
[5:] Again it must be borne in mind that although there are castes among Non-Hindus, as there are among Hindus, caste has not the same social significance for Non-Hindus as it has for Hindus. Ask a Mohammedan or a Sikh
who he is. He tells you that he is a Mohammedan or a Sikh, as the case
may be. He does not tell you his caste, although he has one; and you are
satisfied with his answer. When he tells you that he is a Muslim, you
do not proceed to ask him whether he is a Shiya or a Suni; Sheikh or Saiyad; Khatik or Pinjari. When he tells you he is a Sikh, you do not ask him whether he is Jat or Roda, Mazbi or Ramdasi.
But you are not satisfied, if a person tells you that he is a Hindu.
You feel bound to inquire into his caste. Why? Because so essential is
caste in the case of a Hindu, that without knowing it you do not feel
sure what sort of a being he is.
|
|
[6:] That caste has not the same social significance among Non-Hindus as it has among Hindus is clear, if you take into consideration the consequences which follow breach of caste. There may be castes among Sikhs and Mohammedans,
but the Sikhs and the Mohammedans will not outcast a Sikh or a
Mohammedan if he broke his caste. Indeed, the very idea of
excommunication is foreign to the Sikhs and the Mohammedans. But with
the Hindus the case is entirely different. A Hindu is sure to be
outcasted if he broke caste. This shows the difference in the social
significance of caste to Hindus and Non-Hindus. This is the second point
of difference.
|
|
[7:] But there is also a third and a more important one. Caste
among the non-Hindus has no religious consecration; but among the Hindus
most decidedly it has. Among the Non-Hindus, caste is only a practice,
not a sacred institution. They did not originate it. With them it is
only a survival. They do not regard caste as a religious dogma. Religion
compels the Hindus to treat isolation and segregation of castes as a
virtue. Religion does not compel the Non-Hindus to take the same
attitude towards caste. If Hindus wish to break caste, their religion
will come in their way. But it will not be so in the case of Non-Hindus.
It is, therefore, a dangerous delusion to take comfort in the mere
existence of caste among Non-Hindus, without caring to know what place
caste occupies in their life and whether there are other “organic
filaments” which subordinate the feeling of caste to the feeling of
community. The sooner the Hindus are cured of this delusion, the better.
|
|
[8:] The other set [of “neutral” Hindus] denies that caste presents any problem at all for the Hindus to consider. Such Hindus seek comfort in the view that the Hindus
have survived, and take this as a proof of their fitness to survive. This point of view is well expressed by Prof. S. Radhakrishnan in his Hindu View of Life. Referring to Hinduism he says,
“The civilization itself has not been a short-lived one. Its historic
records date back for over four thousand years and even then it had
reached a stage of civilization which has continued its unbroken, though
at times slow and static, course until the present day. It has stood
the stress and strain of more than four or five millenniums of spiritual
thought and experience. Though peoples of different races and cultures
have been pouring into India from the dawn of History, Hinduism has been
able to maintain its supremacy and even the proselytising creeds backed
by political power have not been able to coerce the large majority of Hindus
to their views. The Hindu culture possesses some vitality which seems
to be denied to some other more forceful currents. It is no more
necessary to dissect Hinduism than to open a tree to see whether the sap
still runs.”
The name of Prof. Radhakrishnan is big enough to invest
with profundity whatever he says, and impress the minds of his readers.
But I must not hesitate to speak out my mind. For I fear that his
statement may become the basis of a vicious argument that the fact of
survival is proof of fitness to survive.
|
|
[9:] It seems to me that the question is not
whether a community lives or dies; the question is on what plane does it
live. There are different modes of survival. But not all are equally
honourable. For an individual as well as for a society, there is a gulf
between merely living, and living worthily. To fight in a battle and to
live in glory is one mode. To beat a retreat, to surrender, and to live
the life of a captive is also a mode of survival. It is useless for a Hindu
to take comfort in the fact that he and his people have survived. What
he must consider is, what is the quality of their survival. If he does
that, I am sure he will cease to take pride in the mere fact of
survival. A Hindu’s life has been a life of continuous defeat, and what
appears to him to be life everlasting is not living everlastingly, but
is really a life which is perishing everlastingly. It is a mode of
survival of which every right-minded Hindu who is not afraid to own up
to the truth will feel ashamed.
20 [The real key to destroying Caste is rejection of the Shastras]
|
|
[1:] There is no doubt, in my opinion, that
unless you change your social order you can achieve little by way of
progress. You cannot mobilize the community either for defence or for
offence. You cannot build anything on the foundations of caste. You
cannot build up a nation, you cannot build up a morality. Anything that
you will build on the foundations of caste will crack, and will never be
a whole.
|
|
[2:] The only question that remains to be considered is—How to bring about the reform of the Hindu social order? How to abolish Caste? This is a question of supreme importance. There is a view that in the reform of Caste, the first step to take is to abolish sub-castes.
This view is based upon the supposition that there is a greater
similarity in manners and status between sub-castes than there is
between castes. I think this is an erroneous supposition. The Brahmins of Northern and Central India are socially of lower grade, as compared with the Brahmins of the Deccan and Southern India.
The former are only cooks and water-carriers, while the latter occupy a
high social position. On the other hand, in Northern India, the
Vaishyas and Kayasthas are intellectually and socially on a par with the Brahmins of the Deccan and Southern India.
|
|
[3:] Again, in the matter of food there is no similarity between the Brahmins of the Deccan and Southern India, who are vegetarians, and the Brahmins of Kashmir and Bengal,
who are non-vegetarians. On the other hand, the Brahmins of the Deccan
and Southern India have more in common so far as food is concerned with
such non-Brahmins as the Gujaratis, Marwaris, Banias, and Jains.
|
|
[4:] There is no doubt that from the standpoint of making the transition from one caste to another easy, the fusion of the Kayasthas of Northern India and the other Non-Brahmins of Southern India with the Non-Brahmins of the Deccan and the Dravidian country
is more practicable than the fusion of the Brahmins of the South with
the Brahmins of the North. But assuming that the fusion of sub-castes
is possible, what guarantee is there that the abolition of sub-castes
will necessarily lead to the abolition of castes? On the contrary, it
may happen that the process may stop with the abolition of sub-castes.
In that case, the abolition of sub-castes will only help to strengthen
the castes, and make them more powerful and therefore more mischievous.
This remedy is therefore neither practicable nor effective, and may
easily prove to be a wrong remedy.
|
|
[5:] Another plan of action for the abolition
of Caste is to begin with inter-caste dinners. This also, in my
opinion, is an inadequate remedy. There are many castes which allow
inter-dining. But it is a common experience that inter-dining has not
succeeded in killing the spirit of Caste and the consciousness of Caste.
I am convinced that the real remedy is inter-marriage. Fusion of blood
can alone create the feeling of being kith and kin, and unless this
feeling of kinship, of being kindred, becomes paramount, the separatist
feeling—the feeling of being aliens—created by Caste will not vanish.
Among the Hindus,
inter-marriage must necessarily be a factor of greater force in social
life than it need be in the life of the non-Hindus. Where society is
already well-knit by other ties, marriage is an ordinary incident of
life. But where society is cut asunder, marriage as a binding force
becomes a matter of urgent necessity. The real remedy for breaking Caste is inter-marriage. Nothing else will serve as the solvent of Caste.
|
|
[6:] Your Jat-Pat-Todak Mandal
has adopted this line of attack. It is a direct and frontal attack, and
I congratulate you upon a correct diagnosis, and more upon your having
shown the courage to tell the Hindus
what is really wrong with them. Political tyranny is nothing compared
to social tyranny, and a reformer who defies society is a much more
courageous man than a politician who defies the government. You are
right in holding that Caste will cease to be an operative force only
when inter-dining and inter-marriage have become matters of common
course. You have located the source of the disease.
|
|
[7:] But is your prescription the right
prescription for the disease? Ask yourselves this question: why is it
that a large majority of Hindus do not inter-dine and do not inter-marry? Why is it that your cause is not popular?
|
|
[8:] There can be only one answer to this
question, and it is that inter-dining and inter-marriage are repugnant
to the beliefs and dogmas which the Hindus
regard as sacred. Caste is not a physical object like a wall of bricks
or a line of barbed wire which prevents the Hindus from commingling and
which has, therefore, to be pulled down. Caste is a notion, it is a
state of the mind. The destruction of Caste does not therefore mean the
destruction of a physical barrier. It means a notional change.
|
|
[9:] Caste may be bad. Caste may lead to
conduct so gross as to be called man’s inhumanity to man. All the same,
it must be recognized that the Hindus
observe Caste not because they are inhuman or wrong-headed. They
observe Caste because they are deeply religious. People are not wrong in
observing Caste. In my view, what is wrong is their religion, which has
inculcated this notion of Caste. If this is correct, then obviously the
enemy you must grapple with is not the people who observe Caste, but
the Shastras
which teach them this religion of Caste. Criticising and ridiculing
people for not inter-dining or inter-marrying, or occasionally holding
inter-caste dinners and celebrating inter-caste marriages, is a futile
method of achieving the desired end. The real remedy is to destroy the
belief in the sanctity of the Shastras.
|
|
[10:] How do you expect to succeed, if you allow the Shastras to continue to mould the beliefs and opinions of the people? Not to question the authority of the Shastras—to
permit the people to believe in their sanctity and their sanctions, and
then to blame the people and to criticise them for their acts as being
irrational and inhuman—is an incongruous way of carrying on social
reform. Reformers working for the removal of untouchability, including Mahatma Gandhi, do not seem to realize that the acts of the people are merely the results of their beliefs inculcated in their minds by the Shastras, and that people will not change their conduct until they cease to believe in the sanctity of the Shastras on which their conduct is founded.
|
|
[11:] No wonder that such efforts have not
produced any results. You also seem to be erring in the same way as the
reformers working in the cause of removing untouchability. To agitate
for and to organise inter-caste dinners and inter-caste marriages is
like forced feeding brought about by artificial means. Make every man
and woman free from the thraldom of the Shastras, cleanse their minds of the pernicious notions founded on the Shastras, and he or she will inter-dine and inter-marry, without your telling him or her to do so.
|
|
[12:] It is no use seeking refuge in quibbles. It is no use telling people that the Shastras do not say what they are believed to say, if they are grammatically read or logically interpreted. What matters is how the Shastras have been understood by the people. You must take the stand that Buddha took. You must take the stand which Guru Nanak took. You must not only discard the Shastras, you must deny their authority, as did Buddha and Nanak. You must have courage to tell the Hindus
that what is wrong with them is their religion—the religion which has
produced in them this notion of the sacredness of Caste. Will you show
that courage?
21 [Internal reform of the Caste System is virtually impossible]
|
|
[1:] What are your chances of success? Social
reforms fall into different species. There is a species of reform which
does not relate to the religious notions of a people, but is purely
secular in character. There is also a species of reform which relates to
the religious notions of a people. Of such a species of reform, there
are two varieties. In one, the reform accords with the principles of the
religion, and merely invites people who have departed from it, to
revert to them and to follow them.
|
|
[2:] The second is a reform which not only
touches the religious principles but is diametrically opposed to those
principles, and invites people to depart from and to discard their
authority, and to act contrary to those principles. Caste is the natural
outcome of certain religious beliefs which have the sanction of the Shastras,
which are believed to contain the command of divinely inspired sages
who were endowed with a supernatural wisdom and whose commands,
therefore, cannot be disobeyed without committing a sin.
|
|
[3:] The destruction of Caste is a reform
which falls under the third category [that is, the second variety of the
second species]. To ask people to give up Caste is to ask them to go
contrary to their fundamental religious notions. It is obvious that the
first and second species of reform are easy. But the third is a
stupendous task, well-nigh impossible. The Hindus
hold to the sacredness of the social order. Caste has a divine basis.
You must therefore destroy the sacredness and divinity with which Caste
has become invested. In the last analysis, this means you must destroy
the authority of the Shastras and the Vedas.
|
|
[4:] I have emphasized this question of the
ways and means of destroying Caste, because I think that knowing the
proper ways and means is more important than knowing the ideal. If you
do not know the real ways and means, all your shots are sure to be
misfires. If my analysis is correct, then your task is herculean. You
alone can say whether you are capable of achieving it.
|
|
[5:] Speaking for myself, I see the task to
be well-nigh impossible. Perhaps you would like to know why I think so.
Out of the many reasons which have led me to take this view, I will
mention some which I regard as most important. One of these reasons is
the attitude of hostility which the Brahmins
have shown towards this question. The Brahmins form the vanguard of the
movement for political reform, and in some cases also of economic
reform. But they are not to be found even as camp-followers in the army
raised to break down the barricades of Caste. Is there any hope of the
Brahmins ever taking up a lead in the future in this matter? I say no.
|
|
[6:] You may ask why. You may argue that there is no reason why Brahmins should continue to shun social reform. You may argue that the Brahmins know that the bane of Hindu
Society is Caste, and as an enlightened class they could not be
expected to be indifferent to its consequences. You may argue that there
are secular Brahmins and priestly Brahmins, and if the latter do not
take up the cudgels on behalf of those who want to break Caste, the
former will.
|
|
[7:] All this of course sounds very plausible. But in all this it is forgotten that the break-up of the Caste system is bound to adversely affect the Brahmin caste. Having regard to this, is it reasonable to expect that the Brahmins
will ever consent to lead a movement, the ultimate result of which is
to destroy the power and prestige of the Brahmin caste? Is it reasonable
to expect the secular Brahmins to take part in a movement directed
against the priestly Brahmins? In my judgment, it is useless to make a
distinction between the secular Brahmins and priestly Brahmins. Both are
kith and kin. They are two arms of the same body, and one is bound to
fight for the existence of the other.
|
|
[8:] In this connection, I am reminded of some very pregnant remarks made by Prof. Dicey in his English Constitution. Speaking of the actual limitation on the legislative supremacy of Parliament, Dicey says:
“The actual exercise of authority by any sovereign whatever, and notably
by Parliament, is bounded or controlled by two limitations. Of these
the one is an external, and the other is an internal limitation. The
external limit to the real power of a sovereign consists in the
possibility or certainty that his subjects or a large number of them
will disobey or resist his laws….The internal limit to the exercise of
sovereignty arises from the nature of the sovereign power itself. Even a
despot exercises his powers in accordance with his character, which is
itself moulded by the circumstance under which he lives, including under
that head the moral feelings of the time and the society to which he
belongs. The Sultan could not, if he woulrfd, change the religion of the
Mohammedan world, but even if he could do so, it is in the very highest
degree improbable that the head of Mohammedanism should wish to
overthrow the religion of Mohammed; the internal check on the exercise
of the Sultan’s power is at least as strong as the external limitation.
People sometimes ask the idle question, why the Pope does not introduce
this or that reform? The true answer is that a revolutionist is not the
kind of man who becomes a Pope and that a man who becomes a Pope has no
wish to be a revolutionist.”
|
|
[9:]
I think these remarks apply equally to the Brahmins
of India, and one can say with equal truth that if a man who becomes a
Pope has no wish to become a revolutionary, a man who is born a Brahmin
has much less desire to become a revolutionary. Indeed, to expect a
Brahmin to be a revolutionary in matters of social reform is as idle as
to expect the British Parliament, as was said by Leslie Stephen, to pass an Act requiring all blue-eyed babies to be murdered.
|
|
[10:] Some of you will say that it is a matter of small concern whether the Brahmins
come forward to lead the movement against Caste or whether they do not.
To take this view is, in my judgment, to ignore the part played by the
intellectual class in the community. Whether you accept the theory of
the great man as the maker of history or whether you do not, this much
you will have to concede: that in every country the intellectual class
is the most influential class, if not the governing class. The
intellectual class is the class which can foresee, it is the class which
can advise and give the lead. In no country does the mass of the people
live the life of intelligent thought and action. It is largely
imitative, and follows the intellectual class.
|
|
[11:] There is no exaggeration in saying
that the entire destiny of a country depends upon its intellectual
class. If the intellectual class is honest, independent, and
disinterested, it can be trusted to take the initiative and give a
proper lead when a crisis arises. It is true that intellect by itself is
no virtue. It is only a means, and the use of means depends upon the
ends which an intellectual person pursues. An intellectual man can be a
good man, but he can easily be a rogue. Similarly an intellectual class
may be a band of high-souled persons, ready to help, ready to emancipate
erring humanity—or it may easily be a gang of crooks, or a body of
advocates for a narrow clique from which it draws its support.
|
|
[12:] You may think it a pity that the intellectual class in India is simply another name for the Brahmin
caste. You may regret that the two are one; that the existence of the
intellectual class should be bound up with one single caste; that this
intellectual class should share the interest and the aspirations of that
Brahmin caste, and should be a class which has regarded itself as the
custodian of the interest of that caste, rather than of the interests of
the country. All this may be very regrettable. But the fact remains
that the Brahmins form the intellectual class of the Hindus. It is not
only an intellectual class, but it is a class which is held in great
reverence by the rest of the Hindus.
|
|
[13:] The Hindus are taught that the Brahmins are Bhudevas (Gods on earth) .
The Hindus are taught that Brahmins alone can be their teachers. Manu
says, “If it be asked how it should be with respect to points of the Dharma which have not been specially mentioned, the answer is, that which Brahmins who are Shishthas propound shall doubtless have legal force”:
|
|
[14:]
|
|
[15:] When such an intellectual class, which
holds the rest of the community in its grip, is opposed to the reform
of Caste, the chances of success in a movement for the break-up of the Caste system appear to me very, very remote.
|
|
[16:] The second reason why I say the task is impossible will be clear, if you will bear in mind that the Caste system
has two aspects. In one of its aspects, it divides men into separate
communities. In its second aspect, it places these communities in a
graded order one above the other in social status. Each caste takes its
pride and its consolation in the fact that in the scale of castes it is
above some other caste. As an outward mark of this gradation, there is
also a gradation of social and religious rights, technically spoken of
as Ashtadhikaras and Sanskaras. The higher the grade of a caste, the greater the number of these rights; and the lower the grade, the lesser their number.
|
|
[17:] Now this gradation, this scaling of castes, makes it impossible to organise a common front against the Caste System.
If a caste claims the right to inter-dine and inter-marry with another
caste placed above it, it is frozen the instant it is told by
mischief-mongers—and there are many Brahmins
amongst such mischief-mongers—that it will have to concede inter-dining
and inter-marriage with castes below it! All are slaves of the Caste
System. But all the slaves are not equal in status.
|
|
[18:] To excite the proletariat to bring about an economic revolution, Karl Marx
told them: “You have nothing to lose except your chains.” But the
artful way in which the social and religious rights are distributed
among the different castes, whereby some have more and some have less,
makes the slogan of Karl Marx quite useless to excite the Hindus against the Caste System.
Castes form a graded system of sovereignties, high and low, which are
jealous of their status and which know that if a general dissolution
came, some of them stand to lose more of their prestige and power than
others do. You cannot, therefore, have a general mobilization of the Hindus (to use a military expression) for an attack on the Caste System.
22 [No reformers, and no appeals to reason, have so far succeeded]
|
|
[1:] Can you appeal to reason, and ask the Hindus
to discard Caste as being contrary to reason? That raises the question:
Is a Hindu free to follow his reason? Manu has laid down three
sanctions to which every Hindu must conform in the matter of his
behaviour:
|
|
[2:]
|
|
[3:] Here there is no place for reason to play its part. A Hindu must follow either Veda, Smriti or sadachar. He cannot follow anything else.
|
|
[4:] In the first place, how are the texts of the Vedas and Smritis
to be interpreted whenever any doubt arises regarding their meaning? On
this important question the view of Manu is quite definite. He says:
|
|
[5:]
|
|
[6:] According to this rule, rationalism as a canon of interpreting the Vedas and Smritis
is absolutely condemned. It is regarded to be as wicked as atheism, and
the punishment provided for it is excommunication. Thus, where a matter
is covered by the Veda or the Smriti, a Hindu cannot resort to rational thinking.
|
|
[7:] Even when there is a conflict between Vedas and Smritis
on matters on which they have given a positive injunction, the solution
is not left to reason. When there is a conflict between two Shrutis,
both are to be regarded as of equal authority. Either of them may be
followed. No attempt is to be made to find out which of the two accords
with reason. This is made clear by Manu:
|
|
[8:]
|
|
[9:] “When there is a conflict between Shruti and Smriti, the Shruti
must prevail.” But here too, no attempt must be made to find out which
of the two accords with reason. This is laid down by Manu in the
following shloka:
|
|
[10:]
|
|
[11:] Again, when there is a conflict between two Smritis, the Manu Smriti must prevail, but no attempt is to be made to find out which of the two accords with reason. This is the ruling given by Brihaspati:
|
|
[12:]
|
|
[13:] It is, therefore, clear that in any matter on which the Shrutis and Smritis have given a positive direction, a Hindu is not free to use his reasoning faculty. The same rule is laid down in the Mahabharat:
|
|
[14:]
|
|
[15:] He must abide by their directions. Caste and Varna are matters which are dealt with by the Vedas and the Smritis, and consequently, appeal to reason can have no effect on a Hindu.
|
|
[16:] So far as Caste and Varna are concerned, not only the Shastras do not permit the Hindu
to use his reason in the decision of the question, but they have taken
care to see that no occasion is left to examine in a rational way the
foundations of his belief in Caste and Varna. It must be a source of
silent amusement to many a Non-Hindu to find hundreds and thousands of
Hindus breaking Caste on certain occasions, such as railway journeys and
foreign travel, and yet endeavouring to maintain Caste for the rest of
their lives!
|
|
[17:] The explanation of this phenomenon
discloses another fetter on the reasoning faculties of the Hindus. Man’s
life is generally habitual and unreflective. Reflective thought—in the
sense of active, persistent, and careful consideration of any belief or
supposed form of knowledge, in the light of the grounds that support it
and the further conclusions to which it tends—is quite rare, and arises
only in a situation which presents a dilemma or a crisis. Railway
journeys and foreign travels are really occasions of crisis in the life
of a Hindu,
and it is natural to expect a Hindu to ask himself why he should
maintain Caste at all, if he cannot maintain it at all times. But he
does not. He breaks Caste at one step, and proceeds to observe it at the
next, without raising any question.
|
|
[18:] The reason for this astonishing conduct is to be found in the rule of the Shastras, which directs him to maintain Caste as far as possible and to undergo prayaschitta when he cannot. By this theory of prayaschitta, the Shastras,
by following a spirit of compromise, have given caste a perpetual lease
on life, and have smothered the reflective thought which would have
otherwise led to the destruction of the notion of Caste.
|
|
[19:] There have been many who have worked
in the cause of the abolition of Caste and Untouchability. Of those who
can be mentioned, Ramanuja, Kabir, and others stand out prominently. Can you appeal to the acts of these reformers and exhort the Hindus to follow them?
|
|
[20:] It is true that Manu has included sadachar as one of the sanctions along with Shruti and Smriti. Indeed, sadachar (
) has been given a higher place than Shastras:
|
|
[21:]
|
|
[22:] According to this, sadachar, whether it is dharmya or adharmya, in accordance with Shastras or contrary to Shastras, must be followed. But what is the meaning of sadachar? If anyone were to suppose that sadachar means right or good acts—i.e., acts of good and righteous men—he would find himself greatly mistaken. Sadachar does not means good acts or acts of good men. It means ancient custom, good or bad. The following verse makes this clear:
|
|
[23:]
|
|
[24:] As though to warn people against the view that sadachar means good acts or acts of good men, and fearing that people might understand it that way and follow the acts of good men, the Smritis have commanded the Hindus in unmistakable terms not to follow even Gods in their good deeds, if they are contrary to Shruti, Smriti, and sadachar. This may sound to be most extraordinary, most perverse, but the fact remains that is an injunction issued to the Hindus by their Shastras.
|
|
[25:] Reason and morality are the two most
powerful weapons in the armoury of a reformer. To deprive him of the use
of these weapons is to disable him for action. How are you going to
break up Caste, if people are not free to consider whether it accords
with reason? How are you going to break up Caste, if people are not free
to consider whether it accords with morality? The wall built around
Caste is impregnable, and the material of which it is built contains
none of the combustible stuff of reason and morality. Add to this the
fact that inside this wall stands the army of Brahmins who form the intellectual class, Brahmins who are the natural leaders of the Hindus,
Brahmins who are there not as mere mercenary soldiers but as an army
fighting for its homeland, and you will get an idea why I think that the
breaking up of Caste among the Hindus is well-nigh impossible. At any
rate, it would take ages before a breach is made.
|
|
[26:] But whether the doing of the deed
takes time or whether it can be done quickly, you must not forget that
if you wish to bring about a breach in the system, then you have got to
apply the dynamite to the Vedas and the Shastras, which deny any part to reason; to the Vedas and Shastras, which deny any part to morality. You must destroy the religion of the Shrutis and the Smritis. Nothing else will avail. This is my considered view of the matter.
23 [Destroying Caste would not destroy the true principles of Religion]
|
|
[1:] Some may not understand what I mean by
destruction of Religion; some may find the idea revolting to them, and
some may find it revolutionary. Let me therefore explain my position. I
do not know whether you draw a distinction between principles and rules.
But I do. Not only do I make a distinction, but I say that this
distinction is real and important. Rules are practical; they are
habitual ways of doing things according to prescription. But principles
are intellectual; they are useful methods of judging things. Rules seek
to tell an agent just what course of action to pursue. Principles do not
prescribe a specific course of action. Rules, like cooking recipes, do
tell just what to do and how to do it. A principle, such as that of
justice, supplies a main heading by reference to which he is to consider
the bearings of his desires and purposes; it guides him in his thinking
by suggesting to him the important consideration which he should bear
in mind.
|
|
[2:] This difference between rules and
principles makes the acts done in pursuit of them different in quality
and in content. Doing what is said to be good by virtue of a rule, and
doing good in the light of a principle, are two different things. The
principle may be wrong, but the act is conscious and responsible. The
rule may be right, but the act is mechanical. A religious act may not be
a correct act, but must at least be a responsible act. To permit of
this responsibility, Religion must mainly be a matter of principles
only. It cannot be a matter of rules. The moment it degenerates into
rules, it ceases to be Religion, as it kills the responsibility which is
the essence of a truly religious act.
|
|
[3:] What is this Hindu Religion? Is it a set of principles, or is it a code of rules? Now the Hindu Religion, as contained in the Vedas and the Smritis,
is nothing but a mass of sacrificial, social, political, and sanitary
rules and regulations, all mixed up. What is called Religion by the
Hindus is nothing but a multitude of commands and prohibitions.
Religion, in the sense of spiritual principles, truly universal,
applicable to all races, to all countries, to all times, is not to be
found in them; and if it is, it does not form the governing part of a
Hindu’s life. That for a Hindu, Dharma means commands and prohibitions, is clear from the way the word Dharma is used in the Vedas and the Smritis and understood by the commentators. The word Dharma as used in the Vedas in most cases means religious ordinances or rites. Even Jaimini in his Purva-Mimamsa defines Dharma as “a desirable goal or result that is indicated by injunctive (Vedic) passages.”
|
|
[4:] To put it in plain language, what the Hindus
call Religion is really Law, or at best legalized class-ethics.
Frankly, I refuse to call this code of ordinances as Religion. The first
evil of such a code of ordinances, misrepresented to the people as
Religion, is that it tends to deprive moral life of freedom and
spontaneity, and to reduce it (for the conscientious, at any rate) to a
more or less anxious and servile conformity to externally imposed rules.
Under it, there is no loyalty to ideals; there is only conformity to
commands.
|
|
[5:] But the worst evil of this code of
ordinances is that the laws it contains must be the same yesterday,
today, and forever. They are iniquitous in that they are not the same
for one class as for another. But this iniquity is made perpetual in
that they are prescribed to be the same for all generations. The
objectionable part of such a scheme is not that they are made by certain
persons called Prophets or Law-givers. The objectionable part is that
this code has been invested with the character of finality and fixity.
Happiness notoriously varies with the conditions and circumstances of a
person, as well as with the conditions of different people and epochs.
That being the case, how can humanity endure this code of eternal laws,
without being cramped and without being crippled?
|
|
[6:] I have, therefore, no hesitation in
saying that such a religion must be destroyed, and I say there is
nothing irreligious in working for the destruction of such a religion.
Indeed I hold that it is your bounden duty to tear off the mask, to
remove the misrepresentation that is caused by misnaming this Law as
Religion. This is an essential step for you. Once you clear the minds of
the people of this misconception, and enable them to realize that what
they are told is Religion is not Religion, but that it is really Law,
you will be in a position to urge its amendment or abolition.
|
|
[7:] So long as people look upon it as
Religion they will not be ready for a change, because the idea of
Religion is generally speaking not associated with the idea of change.
But the idea of law is associated with the idea of change, and when
people come to know that what is called Religion is really Law, old and
archaic, they will be ready for a change, for people know and accept
that law can be changed.
24 [A true priesthood should be based on qualification, not heredity]
|
|
[1:] While I condemn a Religion of Rules, I
must not be understood to hold the opinion that there is no necessity
for a religion. On the contrary, I agree with Burke
when he says that “True religion is the foundation of society, the
basis on which all true Civil Government rests, and both their
sanction.” Consequently, when I urge that these ancient rules of life be
annulled, I am anxious that their place shall be taken by a Religion of
Principles, which alone can lay claim to being a true Religion. Indeed,
I am so convinced of the necessity of Religion that I feel I ought to
tell you in outline what I regard as necessary items in this religious
reform. The following, in my opinion, should be the cardinal items in
this reform:
-
There should be one and only one standard book of Hindu Religion, acceptable to all Hindus and recognized by all Hindus. This of course means that all other books of Hindu religion such as Vedas, Shastras, and Puranas,
which are treated as sacred and authoritative, must by law cease to be
so, and the preaching of any doctrine, religious or social, contained in
these books should be penalized.
-
It would be better if priesthood among Hindus
were abolished. But as this seems to be impossible, the priesthood must
at least cease to be hereditary. Every person who professes to be a Hindu
must be eligible for being a priest. It should be provided by law that
no Hindu shall be entitled to be a priest unless he has passed an
examination prescribed by the State, and holds a sanad from the State permitting him to practise.
-
No ceremony performed by a priest who does not hold a sanad shall be deemed to be valid in law, and it should be made penal [=punishable] for a person who has no sanad to officiate as a priest.
-
A priest should be the servant of the State, and should be subject to
the disciplinary action of the State in the matter of his morals,
beliefs, and worship, in addition to his being subject along with other
citizens to the ordinary law of the land.
-
The number of priests should be limited by law according to the requirements of the State, as is done in the case of the I.C.S.
|
|
[2:] To some, this may sound radical. But to
my mind there is nothing revolutionary in this. Every profession in
India is regulated. Engineers must show proficiency, doctors must show
proficiency, lawyers must show proficiency, before they are allowed to
practise their professions. During the whole of their career, they must
not only obey the law of the land, civil as well as criminal, but they
must also obey the special code of morals prescribed by their respective
professions. The priest’s is the only profession where proficiency is
not required. The profession of a Hindu priest is the only profession which is not subject to any code.
|
|
[3:] Mentally a priest may be an idiot,
physically a priest may be suffering from a foul disease such as
syphilis or gonorrhea, morally he may be a wreck. But he is fit to
officiate at solemn ceremonies, to enter the sanctum sanctorum [=holiest part] of a Hindu temple, and to worship the Hindu God. All this becomes possible among the Hindus
because for a priest it is enough to be born in a priestly caste. The
whole thing is abominable, and is due to the fact that the priestly
class among Hindus is subject neither to law nor to morality. It
recognizes no duties. It knows only of rights and privileges. It is a
pest which divinity seems to have let loose on the masses for their
mental and moral degradation.
|
|
[4:] The priestly class must be brought under
control by some such legislation as I have outlined above. This will
prevent it from doing mischief and from misguiding people. It will
democratise it by throwing it open to everyone. It will certainly help
to kill the Brahminism and will also help to kill Caste, which is
nothing but Brahminism incarnate. Brahminism is the poison which has
spoiled Hinduism. You will succeed in saving Hinduism if you will kill
Brahminism. There should be no opposition to this reform from any
quarter. It should be welcomed even by the Arya Samajists, because this is merely an application of their own doctrine of guna-karma.
|
|
[5:] Whether you do that or you do not, you
must give a new doctrinal basis to your Religion—a basis that will be in
consonance with Liberty, Equality and Fraternity; in short, with
Democracy. I am no authority on the subject. But I am told that for such
religious principles as will be in consonance with Liberty, Equality
and Fraternity, it may not be necessary for you to borrow from foreign
sources, and that you could draw for such principles on the Upanishads.
Whether you could do so without a complete remoulding, a considerable
scraping and chipping off from the ore they contain, is more than I can
say. This means a complete change in the fundamental notions of life. It
means a complete change in the values of life. It means a complete
change in outlook and in attitude towards men and things.
|
|
[6:] It means conversion—but if you do not
like the word, I will say it means new life. But a new life cannot enter
a body that is dead. New life can enter only into a new body. The old
body must die before a new body can come into existence and a new life
can enter into it. To put it simply: the old must cease to be operative
before the new can begin to enliven [=live] and to pulsate. This is what
I meant when I said you must discard the authority of the Shastras, and destroy the religion of the Shastras.
25 [If Hindu Society is to progress, its traditions must be able to evolve]
|
|
[1:] I have kept you too long. It is time I
brought this address to a close. This would have been a convenient point
for me to have stopped. But this would probably be my last address to a
Hindu
audience, on a subject vitally concerning the Hindus. I would therefore
like, before I close, to place before the Hindus, if they will allow
me, some questions which I regard as vital, and invite them seriously to
consider the same.
|
|
[2:] In the first place, the Hindus
must consider whether it is sufficient to take the placid view of the
anthropologist that there is nothing to be said about the beliefs,
habits, morals, and outlooks on life which obtain among the different
peoples of the world, except that they often differ; or whether it is
not necessary to make an attempt to find out what kind of morality,
beliefs, habits, and outlook have worked best and have enabled those who
possessed them to flourish, to grow strong, to people the earth and to
have dominion over it. As is observed by Prof. Carver,
“Morality and religion, as the organised expression of moral approval
and disapproval, must be regarded as factors in the struggle for
existence as truly as are weapons for offence and defence, teeth and
claws, horns and hoofs, furs and feathers. The social group, community,
tribe, or nation, which develops an unworkable scheme of morality or
within which those social acts which weaken it and unfit it for
survival, habitually create the sentiment of approval, while those which
would strengthen and enable it to be expanded habitually create the
sentiment of disapproval, will eventually be eliminated. It is its
habits of approval or disapproval (these are the results of religion and
morality) that handicap it, as really as the possession of two wings on
one side with none on the other will handicap the colony of flies. It
would be as futile in the one case as in the other to argue, that one
system is just as good as another.”
|
|
[3:] Morality and religion, therefore, are
not mere matters of likes and dislikes. You may dislike exceedingly a
scheme of morality which, if universally practised within a nation,
would make that nation the strongest nation on the face of the earth.
Yet in spite of your dislike, such a nation will become strong. You may
like exceedingly a scheme of morality and an ideal of justice which, if
universally practised within a nation, would make it unable to hold its
own in the struggle with other nations. Yet in spite of your admiration,
this nation will eventually disappear. The Hindus must, therefore, examine their religion and their morality in terms of their survival value.
|
|
[4:] Secondly, the Hindus
must consider whether they should conserve the whole of their social
heritage, or select what is helpful and transmit to future generations
only that much and no more. Prof. John Dewey,
who was my teacher and to whom I owe so much, has said: “Every society
gets encumbered with what is trivial, with dead wood from the past, and
with what is positively perverse….As a society becomes more
enlightened, it realizes that it is responsible not to conserve and transmit the whole of its existing achievements, but only such as make for a better future society.” Even Burke,
in spite of the vehemence with which he opposed the principle of change
embodied in the French Revolution, was compelled to admit that “a State
without the means of some change is without the means of its
conservation. Without such means it might even risk the loss of that
part of the constitution which it wished the most religiously to preserve.'’ What Burke said of a State applies equally to a society.
|
|
[5:] Thirdly, the Hindus
must consider whether they must not cease to worship the past as
supplying their ideals. The baneful effects of this worship of the past
are best summed up by Prof. Dewey when he says:
“An individual can live only in the present. The present is not just
something which comes after the past; much less something produced by
it. It is what life is in leaving the past behind it. The study of past
products will not help us to understand the present. A knowledge of the
past and its heritage is of great significance when it enters into the
present, but not otherwise. And the mistake of making the records and
remains of the past the main material of education is that it tends to
make the past a rival of the present and the present a more or less
futile imitation of the past.”
|
|
[6:] The principle which makes little of the
present act of living and growing, naturally looks upon the present as
empty and upon the future as remote. Such a principle is inimical to
progress, and is a hindrance to a strong and a steady current of life.
|
|
[7:] Fourthly, the Hindus must consider whether the time has not come for them to recognize that there is nothing fixed, nothing eternal, nothing sanatan;
that everything is changing, that change is the law of life for
individuals as well as for society. In a changing society, there must be
a constant revolution of old values; and the Hindus must realize that
if there must be standards to measure the acts of men, there must also
be a readiness to revise those standards.
26 [The struggle is yours; I have now decided to leave the Hindu fold]
|
|
[1:] I have to confess that this address has
become too lengthy. Whether this fault is compensated to any extent by
breadth or depth is a matter for you to judge. All I claim is to have
told you candidly my views. I have little to recommend them but some
study and a deep concern in your destiny. If you will allow me to say
it, these views are the views of a man who has been no tool of power, no
flatterer of greatness. They come from one, almost the whole of whose
public exertion has been one continuous struggle for liberty for the
poor and for the oppressed, and whose only reward has been a continuous
shower of calumny and abuse from national journals and national leaders,
for no other reason except that I refuse to join with them in
performing the miracle—I will not say trick—of liberating the oppressed
with the gold of the tyrant, and raising the poor with the cash of the
rich.
|
|
[2:] All this may not be enough to commend my
views. I think they
[=Dr. Ambedkar’s views] are not likely to alter yours. But whether they
do or do not, the responsibility is entirely yours. You must make your
efforts to uproot Caste, if not in my way, then in your way.
|
|
[3:] I am sorry, I will not be with you. I
have decided to change. This is not the place for giving reasons. But
even when I am gone out of your fold, I will watch your movement with
active sympathy, and you will have my assistance for what it may be
worth. Yours is a national cause. Caste is no doubt primarily the breath
of the Hindus. But the Hindus have fouled the air all over, and everybody is infected—Sikh, Muslim,
and Christian. You, therefore, deserve the support of all those who are
suffering from this infection—Sikh, Muslim, and Christian.
|
|
[4:] Yours is more difficult than the other national cause, namely Swaraj.
In the fight for Swaraj you fight with the whole nation on your side.
In this, you have to fight against the whole nation—and that too, your
own. But it is more important than Swaraj. There is no use having
Swaraj, if you cannot defend it. More important than the question of
defending Swaraj is the question of defending the Hindus
under the Swaraj. In my opinion, it is only when Hindu Society becomes a
casteless society that it can hope to have strength enough to defend
itself. Without such internal strength, Swaraj for Hindus may turn out
to be only a step towards slavery. Good-bye, and good wishes for your
success.
A Vindication Of Caste By Mahatma Gandhi
|
(A Reprint of his Articles in the Harijan)
|
|
[1:] Dr. Ambedkar’s Indictment (I)
|
|
[2:] The readers will recall the fact that Dr. Ambedkar was to have presided last May at the annual conference of the Jat-Pat-Todak Mandal of Lahore.
But the conference itself was cancelled because Dr. Ambedkar’s address
was found by the Reception Committee to be unacceptable. How far a
Reception Committee is justified in rejecting a President of its choice
because of his address that may be objectionable to it is open to
question. The Committee knew Dr. Ambedkar’s views on caste and the Hindu
scriptures. They knew also that he had in unequivocal terms decided to
give up Hinduism. Nothing less than the address that Dr. Ambedkar had
prepared was to be expected from him. The committee appears to have
deprived the public of an opportunity of listening to the original views
of a man who has carved out for himself a unique position in society.
Whatever label he wears in future, Dr. Ambedkar is not the man to allow
himself to be forgotten.
|
|
[3:] Dr. Ambedkar was not going to be beaten
by the Reception Committee. He has answered their rejection of him by
publishing the address at his own expense. He has priced it at 8 annas, I would suggest a reduction to 2 annas or at least [=at most] 4 annas.
|
|
[4:] No reformer can ignore the address. The
orthodox will gain by reading it. This is not to say that the address is
not open to objection. It has to be read only because it is open to
serious objection. Dr. Ambedkar is a challenge to Hinduism. Brought up
as a Hindu, educated by a Hindu potentate, he has become so disgusted with the so-called Savarna
Hindus or the treatment that he and his people have received at their
hands that he proposes to leave not only them but the very religion that
is his and their common heritage. He has transferred to that religion,
his disgust against a part of its professors [=believers].
|
|
[5:] But this is not to be wondered at. After
all, one can only judge a system or an institution by the conduct of
its representatives. What is more, Dr. Ambedkar found that the vast
majority of Savarna Hindus
had not only conducted themselves inhumanly against those of their
fellow religionists whom they classed as untouchables, but they had
based their conduct on the authority of their scriptures, and when he
began to search them he had found ample warrant for their beliefs in
untouchability and all its implications. The author of the address has
quoted chapter and verse in proof of his three-fold indictment—inhuman
conduct itself, the unabashed justification for it on the part of the
perpetrators, and the subsequent discovery that the justification was
warranted by their scriptures.
|
|
[6:] No Hindu
who prizes his faith above life itself can afford to underrate the
importance of this indictment. Dr Ambedkar is not alone in his disgust.
He is its most uncompromising exponent and one of the ablest among them.
He is certainly the most irreconcilable among them. Thank God, in the
front rank of the leaders he is singularly alone, and as yet but a
representative of a very small minority. But what he says is voiced with
more or less vehemence by many leaders belonging to the depressed classes. Only the latter, for instance Rao Bahadur M. C. Rajah and Dewan Bahadur Srinivasan,
not only do not threaten to give up Hinduism, but find enough warmth in
it to compensate for the shameful persecution to which the vast mass of
Harijans are exposed.
|
|
[7:] But the fact of many leaders remaining in the Hindu fold is no warrant for disregarding what Dr. Ambedkar has to say. The Savarnas
have to correct their belief and their conduct. Above all, those who
are [preeminent] by their learning and influence among the Savarnas have
to give an authoritative interpretation of the scriptures. The
questions that Dr. Ambedkar’s indictment suggests are:
|
|
[8:]
- What are the scriptures?
- Are
all the printed texts to be regarded as an integral part of them, or is
any part of them to be rejected as unauthorised interpolation?
- What
is the answer of such accepted and expurgated scriptures on the
question of untouchability, caste, equality of status, inter-dining and
intermarriages? (These have been all examined by Dr. Ambedkar in his
address.)
- I must reserve for the next issue my own answer to
these questions and a statement of the (at least some) manifest flaws in
Dr. Ambedkar’s thesis.
(Harijan, July 11, 1936)
|
|
[9:] Dr. Ambedkar’s Indictment (II)
|
|
[10:] The Vedas, Upanishads, Smritis and Puranas, including the Ramayana and the Mahabharata, are the Hindu
Scriptures. Nor is this a finite list. Every age or even generation has
added to the list. It follows, therefore, that everything printed or
even found handwritten is not scripture. The Smritis, for
instance, contain much that can never be accepted as the word of God.
Thus many of the texts that Dr. Ambedkar quotes from the Smritis
cannot be accepted as authentic. The scriptures, properly so-called, can
only be concerned with eternal verities and must appeal to any
conscience, i.e. any heart whose eyes of understanding are opened.
Nothing can be accepted as the word of God which cannot be tested by
reason or be capable of being spiritually experienced. And even when you
have an expurgated edition of the scriptures, you will need their
interpretation. Who is the best interpreter? Not learned men surely.
Learning there must be. But religion does not live by it. It lives in
the experiences of its saints and seers, in their lives and sayings.
When all the most learned commentators of the scriptures are utterly
forgotten, the accumulated experience of the sages and saints will abide
and be an inspiration for ages to come.
|
|
[11:] Caste has nothing to do with religion.
It is a custom whose origin I do not know, and do not need to know for
the satisfaction of my spiritual hunger. But I do know that it is
harmful both to spiritual and national growth. Varna and Ashrama
are institutions which have nothing to do with castes. The law of Varna
teaches us that we have each one of us to earn our bread by following
the ancestral calling. It defines not our rights but our duties. It
necessarily has reference to callings that are conducive to the welfare
of humanity and to no other. It also follows that there is no calling
too low and none too high. All are good, lawful and absolutely equal in
status. The callings of a Brahmin—spiritual
teacher—and a scavenger are equal, and their due performance carries
equal merit before God, and at one time seems to have carried identical
reward before man. Both were entitled to their livelihood and no more.
Indeed one traces even now in the villages the faint lines of this
healthy operation of the law.
|
|
[12:] Living in Segaon with its population of 600, I do not find a great disparity between the earnings of different tradesmen, including Brahmins.
I find too that real Brahmins are to be found, even in these degenerate
days, who are living on alms freely given to them and are giving freely
of what they have of spiritual treasures. It would be wrong and
improper to judge the law of Varna
by its caricature in the lives of men who profess to belong to a Varna,
whilst they openly commit a breach of its only operative rule.
Arrogation of a superior status by and of the Varna over another is a
denial of the law. And there is nothing in the law of Varna to warrant a
belief in untouchability. (The essence of Hinduism is contained in its
enunciation of one and only [one] God as Truth and its bold acceptance
of Ahimsa as the law of the human family.)
|
|
[13:] I am aware that my interpretation of
Hinduism will be disputed by many besides Dr. Ambedkar. That does not
affect my position. It is an interpretation by which I have lived for
nearly half a century, and according to which I have endeavoured to the
best of my ability to regulate my life.
|
|
[14:] In my opinion the profound mistake
that Dr. Ambedkar has made in his address is to pick out the texts of
doubtful authenticity and value, and the state of degraded Hindus
who are no fit specimens of the faith they so woefully misrepresent.
Judged by the standard applied by Dr. Ambedkar, every known living faith
will probably fail.
|
|
[15:] In his able address, the learned Doctor has overproved his case. Can a religion that was professed by Chaitanya, Jnyandeo, Tukaram, Tiruvalluvar, Ramakrishna Paramahansa, Raja Ram Mohan Roy, Maharshi Devendranath Tagore, Vivekanand,
and a host of others who might be easily mentioned, be so utterly
devoid of merit as is made out in Dr. Ambedkar’s address? A religion has
to be judged not by its worst specimens, but by the best it might have
produced. For that and that alone can be used as the standard to aspire
to, if not to improve upon.
(Harijan, July 18, 1936)
|
|
[16:] III: Varna Versus Caste
|
|
[17:] Shri Sant Ramji of the Jat-Pat-Todak Mandal of Lahore wants me to publish the following:
“I have read your remarks about Dr. Ambedkar and the Jat-Pat-Todak Mandal, Lahore. In that connection I beg to submit as follows:
|
|
[18:] We did not invite Dr. Ambedkar to preside over our conference because he belonged to the Depressed Classes, for we do not distinguish between a touchable and an untouchableHindu.
On the contrary our choice fell on him simply because his diagnosis of
the fatal disease of the Hindu community was the same as ours; i.e., he
too was of the opinion that the caste system
was the root cause of the disruption and downfall of the Hindus. The
subject of the Doctor’s thesis for his Doctorate being the caste system,
he has studied the subject thoroughly. Now the object of our conference
was to persuade the Hindus to annihilate castes, but the advice of a
non-Hindu in social and religious matters can have no effect on them.
The Doctor in the supplementary portion of his address insisted on
saying that that was his last speech as a Hindu, which was irrelevant as
well as pernicious to the interests of the conference. So we requested
him to expunge that sentence, for he could easily say the same thing on
any other occasion. But he refused, and we saw no utility in making
merely a show of our function. In spite of all this, I cannot help
praising his address, which is, as far as I know, the most learned
thesis on the subject and worth translating into every vernacular of
India.
|
|
[19:] Moreover, I want to bring to your notice that your philosophical difference between Caste and Varna is too subtle to be grasped by people in general, because for all practical purposes in the Hindu
society Caste and Varna are one and the same thing, for the function of
both of them is one and the same, i.e. to restrict inter-caste
marriages and inter-dining. Your theory of Varnavyavastha
is impracticable in this age, and there is no hope of its revival in
the near future. But Hindus are slaves of caste, and do not want to
destroy it. So when you advocate your ideal of imaginary Varnavyavastha,
they find justification for clinging to caste. Thus you are doing a
great disservice to social reform by advocating your imaginary utility
of the division of Varnas, for it creates a hindrance in our way. To try
to remove untouchability without striking at the root of Varnavyavastha
is simply to treat the outward symptoms of a disease, or to draw a line
on the surface of water. As in the heart of their hearts Dvijas do not want to give social equality to the so-called touchable and untouchable
Shudras, so they refuse to break caste—and give liberal donations for
the removal of untouchability simply to evade the issue. To seek the
help of the Shastras for the removal of untouchability and caste is simply to wash mud with mud.”
|
|
[20:] The last paragraph of the letter surely cancels the first. If the Mandal rejects the help of the Shastras,
they do exactly what Dr. Ambedkar does, i.e. cease to be Hindus. How
then can they object to Dr. Ambedkar’s address merely because he said
that that was his last speech as a Hindu? The position appears to be wholly untenable, especially when the Mandal, for which Shri Sant Ram claims to speak, applauds the whole argument of Dr. Ambedkar’s address.
|
|
[21:] But it is pertinent to ask what the Mandal believes, if it rejects the Shastras. How can a Muslim remain one if he rejects the Quran, or a Christian remain Christian if he rejects the Bible? If Caste and Varna are convertible terms, and if Varna is an integral part of the Shastras which define Hinduism, I do not know how a person who rejects Caste, i.e. Varna, can call himself a Hindu.
|
|
[22:] Shri Sant Ram likens the Shastras to mud. Dr. Ambedkar has not, so far as I remember, given any such picturesque name to the Shastras. I have certainly meant when I have said: that if Shastras support the existing untouchability I should cease to call myself a Hindu. Similarly, if the Shastras
support caste as we know it today in all its hideousness, I may not
call myself or remain a Hindu, since I have no scruples about
interdining or intermarriage. I need not repeat my position regarding Shastras
and their interpretation. I venture to suggest to Shri Sant Ram that it
is the only rational and correct and morally defensible position, and
it has ample warrant in Hindu tradition.
(Harijan, August 15, 1936)
A Reply to the Mahatma by Dr. B. R. Ambedkar
|
|
[1:] 1
I appreciate greatly the honour done me by the Mahatma in taking notice in his Harijan of the speech on Caste which I had prepared for the Jat-Pat-Todak Mandal.
From a perusal of his review of my speech, it is clear that the Mahatma
completely dissents from the views I have expressed on the subject of
Caste. I am not in the habit of entering into controversy with my
opponents unless there are special reasons which compel me to act
otherwise. Had my opponent been some mean and obscure person, I would
not have pursued him. But my opponent being the Mahatma himself, I feel I
must attempt to meet the case to the contrary which he has sought to
put forth.
|
|
[2:] While I appreciate the honour he has done me, I must confess to a sense of surprise on finding that of all people the Mahatma
should accuse me of a desire to seek publicity, as he seems to do when
he suggests that in publishing the undelivered speech my object was to
see that I was not “forgotten.” Whatever the Mahatma may choose to say,
my object in publishing the speech was to provoke the Hindus
to think, and to take stock of their position. I have never hankered
for publicity, and if I may say so, I have more of it than I wish or
need. But supposing it was out of the motive of gaining publicity that I
printed the speech, who could cast a stone at me? Surely not those who,
like the Mahatma, live in glass houses.
|
|
[3:] 2
Motive apart, what has the Mahatma
to say on the question raised by me in the speech? First of all, anyone
who reads my speech will realize that the Mahatma has entirely missed
the issues raised by me, and that the issues he has raised are not the
issues that arise out of what he is pleased to call my indictment of the
Hindus. The principal points which I have tried to make out in my
speech may be catalogued as follows:
|
|
[4:]
- That Caste has ruined the Hindus;
- That the reorganization of the Hindu Society on the basis of Chaturvarnya is impossible because the Varnavyavastha
is like a leaky pot or like a man running at the nose. It is incapable
of sustaining itself by its own virtue, and has an inherent tendency to
degenerate into a Caste System unless there is a legal sanction behind it which can be enforced against everyone transgressing his Varna;
- That the reorganization of the Hindu Society on the basis of Chaturvarnya would be harmful, because the effect of the Varnavyavastha
would be to degrade the masses by denying them opportunity to acquire
knowledge, and to emasculate them by denying them the right to be armed;
- That the Hindu Society must be reorganized on a religious basis which would recognise the principles of Liberty, Equality and Fraternity;
- That in order to achieve this object the sense of religious sanctity behind Caste and Varna must be destroyed;
- That the sanctity of Caste and Varna can be destroyed only by discarding the divine authority of the Shastras.
|
|
[5:] It will be noticed that the questions raised by the Mahatma are absolutely beside the point, and show that the main argument of the speech was lost upon him.
|
|
[6:] 3
Let me examine the substance of the points made by the Mahatma.
The first point made by the Mahatma is that the texts cited by me are
not authentic. I confess I am no authority on this matter. But I should
like to state that the texts cited by me are all taken from the writings
of the late Mr. Tilak, who was a recognised authority on the Sanskrit language and on the Hindu Shastras. His second point is that these Shastras should be interpreted not by the learned but by the saints; and that as the saints have understood them, the Shastras do not support Caste and Untouchability.
|
|
[7:] As regards the first point, what I would like to ask the Mahatma
is, what does it avail to anyone if the texts are interpolations, and
if they have been differently interpreted by the saints? The masses do
not make any distinction between texts which are genuine and texts which
are interpolations. The masses do not know what the texts are. They are
too illiterate to know the contents of the Shastras. They have believed what they have been told, and what they have been told is that the Shastras do enjoin as a religious duty the observance of Caste and Untouchability.
|
|
[8:] With regard to the saints, one must
admit that howsoever different and elevating their teachings may have
been as compared to those of the merely learned, they have been
lamentably ineffective. They have been ineffective for two reasons.
Firstly, none of the saints ever attacked the Caste System.
On the contrary—they were staunch believers in the System of Castes.
Most of them lived and died as members of the castes to which they
respectively belonged. So passionately attached was Jnyandeo to his status as a Brahmin that when the Brahmins of Paithan
would not admit him to their fold, he moved heaven and earth to get his
status as a Brahmin recognized by the Brahmin fraternity.
|
|
[9:] And even the saint Eknath, who now figures in the film “Dharmatma“ as a hero for having shown the courage to touch the untouchables
and dine with them, did so not because he was opposed to Caste and
Untouchability, but because he felt that the pollution caused thereby
could be washed away by a bath in the sacred waters of the river Ganges [].
The saints have never, according to my study, carried on a campaign
against Caste and Untouchability. They were not concerned with the
struggle between men. They were concerned with the relation between man
and God. They did not preach that all men were equal. They preached that
all men were equal in the eyes of God—a very different and a very
innocuous proposition, which nobody can find difficult to preach or
dangerous to believe in.
|
|
[10:] The second reason why the teachings of
the saints proved ineffective was because the masses have been taught
that a saint might break Caste, but the common man must not. A saint
therefore never became an example to follow. He always remained a pious
man to be honoured. That the masses have remained staunch believers in
Caste and Untouchability shows that the pious lives and noble sermons of
the saints have had no effect on their life and conduct, as against the
teachings of the Shastras. Thus it can be a matter of no consolation that there were saints, or that there is a Mahatma who understands the Shastras differently from the learned few or ignorant many.
|
|
[11:] That the masses hold a different view of the Shastras is a fact which should and must be reckoned with. How that is to be dealt with, except by denouncing the authority of the Shastras
which continue to govern their conduct, is a question which the Mahatma
has not considered. But whatever the plan the Mahatma puts forth as an
effective means to free the masses from the teachings of the Shastras,
he must accept that the pious life led by one good Samaritan may be
very elevating to himself, but in India, with the attitude the common
man has to saints and to Mahatmas—to honour but not to follow—one cannot
make much out of it.
|
|
[12:] 4
The third point made by the Mahatma is that a religion professed by Chaitanya, Jnyandeo, Tukaram, Tiruvalluvar,
Ramkrishna Paramahansa, etc., cannot be devoid of merit as is made out
by me, and that a religion has to be judged not by its worst specimens
but by the best it might have produced. I agree with every word of this
statement. But I do not quite understand what the Mahatma wishes to
prove thereby. That religion should be judged not by its worst specimens
but by its best is true enough, but does it dispose of the matter? I
say it does not.
|
|
[13:] The question still remains, why the
worst number so many and the best so few. To my mind there are two
conceivable answers to this question: (1) That the worst by reason of
some original perversity of theirs are morally uneducable, and are
therefore incapable of making the remotest approach to the religious
ideal. Or: (2) That the religious ideal is a wholly wrong ideal which
has given a wrong moral twist to the lives of the many, and that the
best have become best in spite of the wrong ideal—in fact, by giving to
the wrong twist a turn in the right direction.
|
|
[14:] Of these two explanations I am not prepared to accept the first, and I am sure that even the Mahatma
will not insist upon the contrary. To my mind the second is the only
logical and reasonable explanation, unless the Mahatma has a third
alternative to explain why the worst are so many and the best so few. If
the second is the only explanation, then obviously the argument of the
Mahatma that a religion should be judged by its best followers carries
us nowhere—except to pity the lot of the many who have gone wrong
because they have been made to worship wrong ideals.
|
|
[15:] 5
The argument of the Mahatma
that Hinduism would be tolerable if only many were to follow the
example of the saints is fallacious for another reason. (In this
connection, see the illuminating article on “Morality and the Social
Structure” by Mr. H. N. Brailsford in the Aryan Path for April 1936.) By citing the names of such illustrious persons as Chaitanya, etc,. what the Mahatma seems to me to suggest in its broadest and simplest form is that Hindu society can be made tolerable and even happy without any fundamental change in its structure, if all the high-caste Hindus
can be persuaded to follow a high standard of morality in their
dealings with the low-caste Hindus. I am totally opposed to this kind of
ideology.
|
|
[16:] I can respect those of the caste Hindus
who try to realize a high social ideal in their life. Without such men,
India would be an uglier and a less happy place to live in than it is.
But nonetheless, anyone who relies on an attempt to turn the members of
the caste Hindus
into better men by improving their personal character is, in my
judgment, wasting his energy and hugging an illusion. Can personal
character make the maker of armaments a good man, i.e., a man who will
sell shells that will not burst and gas that will not poison? If it
cannot, how can you accept personal character [as sufficient] to make a
man loaded with the consciousness of Caste a good man, i.e., a man who
would treat his fellow-men as his friends and equals? To be true to
himself, he must deal with his fellow-man either as a superior or
inferior, according as the case may be; at any rate, differently from
his own caste-fellows. He can never be expected to deal with his
fellow-men as his kinsmen and equals.
|
|
[17:] As a matter of fact, a Hindu
does treat all those who are not of his caste as though they were
aliens, who could be discriminated against with impunity, and against
whom any fraud or trick may be practised without shame. This is to say that there can be a better or a worse Hindu. But a good Hindu there cannot be.
This is so not because there is anything wrong with his personal
character. In fact what is wrong is the entire basis of his relationship
to his fellows. The best of men cannot be moral if the basis of
relationship between them and their fellows is fundamentally a wrong
relationship. To a slave, his master may be better or worse. But there
cannot be a good master. A good man cannot be a master, and a master
cannot be a good man.
|
|
[18:] The same applies to the relationship
between high-caste and low-caste. To a low-caste man, a high-caste man
can be better or worse as compared to other high-caste men. A high-caste
man cannot be a good man, insofar as he must have a low-caste man to
distinguish him as a high-caste man. It cannot be good to a low-caste
man to be conscious that there is a high-caste man above him. I have
argued in my speech that a society based on Varna or Caste is a society which is based on a wrong relationship. I had hoped that the Mahatma would attempt to demolish my argument. But instead of doing that, he has merely reiterated his belief in Chaturvarnya without disclosing the ground on which it is based.
|
|
[19:] 6
Does the Mahatma
practise what he preaches? One does not like to make personal reference
in an argument which is general in its application. But when one
preaches a doctrine and holds it as a dogma, there is a curiosity to
know how far he practises what he preaches. It may be that his failure
to practise is due to the ideal being too high to be attainable; it may
be that his failure to practise is due to the innate hypocrisy of the
man. In any case he exposes his conduct to examination, and I must not
be blamed if I ask, how far has the Mahatma attempted to realize his
ideal in his own case?
|
|
[20:] The Mahatma is a Bania by birth. His ancestors had abandoned trading in favour of ministership, which is a calling of the Brahmins. In his own life, before he became a Mahatma,
when the occasion came for him to choose his career he preferred law to
[a merchant’s] scales. On abandoning law, he became half saint and half
politician. He has never touched trading, which is his ancestral
calling.
|
|
[21:] His youngest son—I take one who is a faithful follower
of his father—was born a Vaishya, has married a Brahmin’s daughter, and has chosen to serve a newspaper magnate. The Mahatma is not
known to have condemned him for not following his ancestral calling. It may be wrong and
uncharitable to judge an ideal by its worst specimens. But surely the Mahatma as a specimen
has no better [=cannot be improved upon], and if he even [=even he] fails to realize the ideal
then the
ideal must be an impossible ideal, quite opposed to the practical instincts of man.
|
|
[22:] Students of Carlyle know that he often spoke on a subject before he thought about it. I wonder whether such has not been the case with the Mahatma,
in regard to the subject matter of Caste. Otherwise, certain questions
which occur to me would not have escaped him. When can a calling be
deemed to have become an ancestral calling, so as to make it binding on a
man? Must a man follow his ancestral calling even if it does not suit
his capacities, even when it has ceased to be profitable? Must a man
live by his ancestral calling even if he finds it to be immoral? If
everyone must pursue his ancestral calling, then it must follow that a
man must continue to be a pimp because his grandfather was a pimp, and a
woman must continue to be a prostitute because her grandmother was a
prostitute. Is the Mahatma prepared to accept the logical conclusion of
his doctrine? To me his ideal of following one’s ancestral calling is
not only an impossible and impractical ideal, but it is also morally an
indefensible ideal.
|
|
[23:] 7
The Mahatma sees great virtue in a Brahmin
remaining a Brahmin all his life. Leaving aside the fact there are many
Brahmins who do not like to remain Brahmins all their lives, what can
we say about those Brahmins who have clung to their ancestral calling of
priesthood? Do they do so from any faith in the virtue of the principle
of ancestral calling, or do they do so from motives of filthy lucre?
The Mahatma does not seem to concern himself with such queries. He is
satisfied that these are “real Brahmins who are living on alms freely
given to them, and giving freely what they have of spiritual treasures.”
This is how a hereditary Brahmin priest appears to the Mahatma—a
carrier of spiritual treasures.
|
|
[24:] But another portrait of the hereditary Brahmin can also be drawn. A Brahmin can be a priest to Vishnu—the God of Love. He can be a priest to Shankar—the God of Destruction. He can be a priest at Buddha Gaya worshipping Buddha—the greatest teacher of mankind, who taught the noblest doctrine of Love. He also can be a priest to Kali,
the Goddess, who must have a daily sacrifice of an animal to satisfy
her thirst for blood. He will be a priest of the temple of Rama—the Kshatriya God! He will also be a priest of the Temple of Parshuram, the God who took on an Avatar to destroy the Kshatriyas! He can be a priest to Bramha, the Creator of the world. He can be a priest to a Pir, whose God Allah
will not brook the claim of Bramha to share his spiritual dominion over
the world! No one can say that this is a picture which is not true to
life.
|
|
[25:] If this is a true picture, one does
not know what to say of this capacity to bear loyalties to Gods and
Goddesses whose attributes are so antagonistic that no honest man can be
a devotee to all of them. The Hindus
rely upon this extraordinary phenomenon as evidence of the greatest
virtue of their religion—namely, its catholicity, its spirit of
toleration. As against this facile view, it can be urged that what is
[described as] toleration and catholicity may be really nothing more
creditable than indifference or flaccid latitudinarianism. These two
attitudes are hard to distinguish in their outer seeming. But they are
so vitally unlike in their real quality that no one who examines them
closely can mistake one for the other.
|
|
[26:] That a man is ready to render homage
to many Gods and
Goddesses may be cited as evidence of his tolerant spirit. But can it
not also be evidence of an insincerity born of a desire to serve the
times? I am sure that this toleration is merely insincerity. If this
view is well founded, one may ask: what spiritual treasure can there be
within a person who is ready to be a priest and a devotee to any deity
which it serves his purpose to worship and to adore? Not only must such a
person be deemed to be bankrupt of all spiritual treasures, but for him
to practice so elevating a profession as that of a priest simply
because it is ancestral—without faith, without belief, merely as a
mechanical process handed down from father to son—is not a conservation
of virtue; it is really the prostitution of a noble profession which is
no other than the service of religion.
|
|
[27:] 8
Why does the Mahatma
cling to the theory of everyone following his or her ancestral calling?
He gives his reasons nowhere. But there must be some reason, although
he does not care to avow it. Years ago, writing on “Caste versus Class”
in his Young India, he argued that the Caste System
was better than a Class System on the ground that Caste was the best
possible adjustment for social stability. If that be the reason why the
Mahatma clings to the theory of everyone following his or her ancestral
calling, then he is clinging to a false view of social life.
|
|
[28:] Everybody wants social stability, and
some adjustment must be made in the relationship between individuals and
classes in order that stability may be had. But two things, I am sure,
nobody wants. One thing nobody wants is a static relationship, something
that is unalterable, something that is fixed for all times. Stability
is wanted, but not at the cost of change when change is imperative. The
second thing nobody wants is mere adjustment. Adjustment is wanted, but
not at the sacrifice of social justice.
|
|
[29:] Can it be said that the adjustment of
social relationships on the basis of caste—i.e,. on the basis of each to
his hereditary calling—avoids these two evils? I am convinced that it
does not. Far from being the best possible adjustment, I have no doubt
that it is of the worst possible kind, inasmuch as it offends against
both the canons of social adjustment—namely, fluidity and equity.
|
|
[30:] 9
Some might think that the Mahatma has made much progress, inasmuch as he now only believes in Varna and does not believe in Caste. It is true that there was a time when the Mahatma was a full-blooded and a blue-blooded Sanatani Hindu. He believed in the Vedas, the Upanishads, the Puranas, and all that goes by the name of Hindu scriptures; and therefore, in Avatars
and rebirth. He believed in Caste, and defended it with the vigour of
the orthodox. He condemned the cry for inter-dining, inter-drinking, and
inter-marrying, and argued that restraints about inter-dining to a
great extent “helped the cultivation of will-power and the conservation
of a certain social virtue.”
|
|
[31:] It is good that he has repudiated this
sanctimonious nonsense and admitted that Caste “is harmful both to
spiritual and national growth,” and maybe his son’s marriage outside his
caste has had something to do with this change of view. But has the Mahatma really progressed? What is the nature of the Varna for which the Mahatma stands? Is it the Vedic conception as commonly understood and preached by Swami Dayanand Saraswati and his followers, the Arya Samajists?
The essence of the Vedic conception of Varna is the pursuit of a
calling which is appropriate to one’s natural aptitude. The essence of
the Mahatma’s conception of Varna is the pursuit of one’s ancestral
calling, irrespective of natural aptitude.
|
|
[32:] What is the difference between Caste and Varna, as understood by the Mahatma?
I find none. As defined by the Mahatma, Varna becomes merely a
different name for Caste, for the simple reason that it is the same in
essence—namely, pursuit of [one’s] ancestral calling. Far from making
progress, the Mahatma has suffered retrogression. By putting this
interpretation upon the Vedic conception of Varna, he has really made
ridiculous what was sublime. While I reject the Vedic Varnavyavastha for reasons given in the speech, I must admit that the Vedic theory of Varna as interpreted by Swami Dayanand
and some others is a sensible and an inoffensive thing. It did not
admit birth as a determining factor in fixing the place of an individual
in society. It only recognized worth.
|
|
[33:] The Mahatma’s view of Varna
not only makes nonsense of the Vedic Varna, but it makes it an
abominable thing. Varna and Caste are two very different concepts. Varna
is based on the principle of each according to his worth, while Caste
is based on the principle of each according to his birth. The two are as
distinct as chalk is from cheese. In fact there is an antithesis
between the two. If the Mahatma believes, as he does, in everyone
following his or her ancestral calling, then most certainly he is
advocating the Caste System,
and in calling it the Varna System he is not only guilty of
terminological inexactitude, but he is causing confusion worse
confounded.
|
|
[34:] I am sure that all his confusion is due to the fact that the Mahatma has no definite and clear conception as to what is Varna
and what is Caste, and as to the necessity of either for the
conservation of Hinduism. He has said—and one hopes that he will not
find some mystic reason to change his view—that Caste is not the essence
of Hinduism. Does he regard Varna as the essence of Hinduism? One
cannot as yet give any categorical answer.
|
|
[35:] Readers of his article on “Dr. Ambedkar’s Indictment” will answer “No.” In that article he does not say that the dogma of Varna
is an essential part of the creed of Hinduism. Far from making Varna
the essence of Hinduism, he says “the essence of Hinduism is contained
in its enunciation of one and only God as Truth and its bold acceptance
of Ahimsa as the law of the human family.”
|
|
[36:] But readers of his article in reply to Mr. Sant Ram will say “Yes.” In that article he says “How can a Muslim remain one if he rejects the Quran, or a Christian remain Christian if he rejects the Bible? If Caste and Varna are convertible terms, and if Varna is an integral part of the Shastras which define Hinduism, I do not know how a person who rejects Caste, i.e. Varna, can call himself a Hindu.” Why this prevarication? Why does the Mahatma
hedge? Whom does he want to please? Has the saint failed to sense the
truth? Or does the politician stand in the way of the saint?
|
|
[37:] The real reason why the Mahatma
is suffering from this confusion is probably to be traced to two
sources. The first is the temperament of the Mahatma. He has in almost
everything the simplicity of the child, with the child’s capacity for
self-deception. Like a child, he can believe in anything he wants to
believe in. We must therefore wait till such time as it pleases the
Mahatma to abandon his faith in Varna, as it has pleased him to abandon his faith in Caste.
|
|
[38:] The second source of confusion is the double role which the Mahatma
wants to play—of a Mahatma and a politician. As a Mahatma, he may be
trying to spiritualize politics. Whether he has succeeded in it or not,
politics have certainly commercialized him. A politician must know that
Society cannot bear the whole truth, and that he must not speak the
whole truth; if he is speaking the whole truth it is bad for his
politics. The reason why the Mahatma is always supporting Caste and Varna
is because he is afraid that if he opposed them he would lose his place
in politics. Whatever may be the source of this confusion, the Mahatma
must be told that he is deceiving himself, and also deceiving the
people, by preaching Caste under the name of Varna.
|
|
[39:] 10
The Mahatma says that the standards I have applied to test Hindus
and Hinduism are too severe, and that judged by those standards every
known living faith will probably fail. The complaint that my standards
are high may be true. But the question is not whether they are high or
whether they are low. The question is whether they are the right
standards to apply. A people and their Religion must be judged by social
standards based on social ethics. No other standard would have any
meaning, if Religion is held to be a necessary good for the well-being
of the people.
|
|
[40:] Now, I maintain that the standards I have applied to test Hindus
and Hinduism are the most appropriate standards, and that I know of
none that are better. The conclusion that every known religion would
fail if tested by my standards may be true. But this fact should not
give the Mahatma as the champion of Hindus
and Hinduism a ground for comfort, any more than the existence of one
madman should give comfort to another madman, or the existence of one
criminal should give comfort to another criminal.
|
|
[41:] I would like to assure the Mahatma that it is not the mere failure of the Hindus
and Hinduism which has produced in me the feelings of disgust and
contempt with which I am charged [=filled]. I realize that the world is a
very imperfect world, and anyone who wants to live in it must bear with
its imperfections.
|
|
[42:] But while I am prepared to bear with
the imperfections and shortcomings of the society in which I may be
destined to labour, I feel I should not consent to live in a society
which cherishes wrong ideals, or a society which, having right ideals,
will not consent to bring its social life into conformity with those
ideals. If I am disgusted with Hindus and Hinduism, it is because I am convinced that they cherish wrong ideals and live a wrong social life. My quarrel with Hindus and Hinduism is not over the imperfections of their social conduct. It is much more fundamental. It is over their ideals.
|
|
[43:] 11
Hindu
society seems to me to stand in need of a moral regeneration which it
is dangerous to postpone. And the question is, who can determine and
control this moral regeneration? Obviously, only those who have
undergone an intellectual regeneration, and those who are honest enough
to have the courage of their convictions born of intellectual
emancipation. Judged by this standard, the Hindu leaders who count are,
in my opinion, quite unfit for the task. It is impossible to say that
they have undergone the preliminary intellectual regeneration. If they
had undergone an intellectual regeneration, they would neither delude
themselves in the simple way of the untaught multitude, nor would they
take advantage of the primitive ignorance of others as one sees them
doing.
|
|
[44:] Notwithstanding the crumbling state of Hindu
society, these leaders will nevertheless unblushingly appeal to ideals
of the past which have in every way ceased to have any connection with
the present—ideals which, however suitable they might have been in the
days of their origin, have now become a warning rather than a guide.
They still have a mystic respect for the earlier forms which makes them
disinclined—nay, opposed—to any examination of the foundations of their
Society. The Hindu masses are of course incredibly heedless in the
formation of their beliefs. But so are the Hindu leaders. And what is
worse is that these Hindu leaders become filled with an illicit passion
for their beliefs when anyone proposes to rob them of their [beliefs’]
companionship.
|
|
[45:] The Mahatma
is no exception. The Mahatma appears not to believe in thinking. He
prefers to follow the saints. Like a conservative with his reverence for
consecrated notions, he is afraid that if he once starts thinking, many
ideals and institutions to which he clings will be doomed. One must
sympathize with him. For every act of independent thinking puts some
portion of an apparently stable world in peril.
|
|
[46:] But it is equally true that dependence
on saints cannot lead us to know the truth. The saints are after all
only human beings, and as Lord Balfour said, “the human mind is no more a
truth-finding apparatus than the snout of a pig.” Insofar as he [=the
Mahatma] does think, to me he really appears to be prostituting his
intelligence to find reasons for supporting this archaic social
structure of the Hindus. He is the most influential apologist of it, and
therefore the worst enemy of the Hindus.
|
|
[47:] Unlike the Mahatma, there are Hindu
leaders who are not content merely to believe and follow. They dare to
think, and act in accordance with the result of their thinking. But
unfortunately they are either a dishonest lot, or an indifferent lot
when it comes to the question of giving right guidance to the mass of
the people. Almost every Brahmin has transgressed the rule of Caste. The
number of Brahmins
who sell shoes is far greater than those who practise priesthood. Not
only have the Brahmins given up their ancestral calling of priesthood
for trading, but they have entered trades which are prohibited to them
by the Shastras. Yet how many Brahmins who break Caste every day will preach against Caste and against the Shastras?
|
|
[48:] For one honest Brahmin preaching against Caste and Shastras
because his practical instinct and moral conscience cannot support a
conviction in them, there are hundreds who break Caste and trample upon
the Shastras every day, but who are the most fanatic upholders of the theory of Caste and the sanctity of the Shastras.
Why this duplicity? Because they feel that if the masses are
emancipated from the yoke of Caste, they would be a menace to the power
and prestige of the Brahmins
as a class. The dishonesty of this intellectual class, who would deny
the masses the fruits of their [=the Brahmins’] thinking, is a most
disgraceful phenomenon.
|
|
[49:] The Hindus, in the words of Matthew Arnold, are “wandering between two worlds, one dead, the other powerless to be born.” What are they to do? The Mahatma
to whom they appeal for guidance does not believe in thinking, and can
therefore give no guidance which can be said to stand the test of
experience. The intellectual classes to whom the masses look for
guidance are either too dishonest or too indifferent to educate them in
the right direction. We are indeed witnesses to a great tragedy. In the
face of this tragedy all one can do is to lament and say—such are thy
Leaders, O Hindus!
Congress ties itself in knots over quota issue
A day after distancing itself from law minister Salman Khurshid’s
remarks on reservation, Congress on Saturday tied itself in knots saying
it favoured further increase in job quotas for backward minorities in
poll-bound Uttar Pradesh.
The Congress also said that it was of the opinion that
there should not have been a ban on the Centre’s decision on
4.5% reservation for minorities in jobs as it was taken prior to poll
announcement.
The Election Commission had directed the Centre to
put on hold the implementation of its decision on job quotas for
minorities in the five poll-bound states.
Khurshid had triggered off a controversy by promising to increase the
sub-quota for OBC Muslims in Uttar Pradesh by 9%, a remark dubbed by
Congress spokesperson Rashid Alvi on Friday as the “individual view” of
the law minister.
“It is an individual view. It would be better if you ask Khurshid for
his reaction in the matter. There is inner party democracy in our
party”, Alvi had said on Friday in response to a volley of questions
including whether the party saw nothing wrong with the minister’s
statement.
On Saturday, Alvi said the Congress party, in its 2009 Lok Sabha
election manifesto, had promised to provide reservation to OBC Muslims
on the lines it had done in Andhra Pradesh.
“The manifesto for Uttar Pradesh elections is being readied … we
are discussing to increase this (4.5%)%age and that will be in our
manfiesto for UP elections,” he said.
On the EC decision, Alvi said “though the EC has put the reservation
decision on hold, we are of the view that any party which goes to polls
will find itself in a difficult position if it does not talk about its
manifesto.”
Alvi said that Khurshid called him on Saturday morning and clarified
that he had not mentioned any definitive figure like 9% but talked about
it being between 8 to 9% and that after calculations it will be part
of the manifesto.
“Our view is that Election Commission has the responsibility to
conduct fair polls in the country. EC is a constitutional body and it
should be beyond criticism. We will not comment on its orders even if
anything goes against us.
“…But our opinion is that we had announced the decision (on 4.5%
reservation for backward Muslims) well before the election dates were
announced. According to us, there should not have been any ban on that
decision,” Alvi said.
He, however, evaded direct answers on specific queries on whether it
was proper for the law minister to announce a figure even before the
manifesto for the state election was out.
“It has to be caluclated. I can’t say how much it would be. But
Salman Khurshid is also the chairman of the manifiesto committee for the
state,” Alvi pointed out suggesting Khurshid might have said it as he
was aware of what was being finalized in the party manifesto.
Sources in AICC meanwhile said the party is likely to announce an
enhance 8.5% reservation for backward minorities in Uttar Pradesh.
Asked why he distanced himself from Khurshid’s Friday remarks, Alvi
merely said,”we do not say anything different from what we decide in our
manfiesto”.
He said the party, as promised in its 2009 Lok Sabha election
manifesto, will provide reservation to backward minorities everywhere
including Uttar Pradesh on the line of Andhra Pradesh and Kerala.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|